Is the Invisible Hand Self-Interest?
“Primal Rambler” writes on Rampage Liberty HERE
“For those unfamiliar with the
invisible hand, it’s a metaphor popularized by Adam Smith in the mid
18th century for how free markets are guided (not controlled). The
invisible hand is an individuals’ self interest. The theory being pushed is
that in a free market people’s self interest is channeled into socially
desireable ends.
Your
mileage on the theory may vary, but it’s worth considering.“It’s not from the
benevolence of the butcher, the
brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner,
but
from their regard for their own interest (Adam Smith, “Wealth of Nations”).
Comment
Primal
Rambler is obviously confident that he knows what Adam Smith meant when he used
the metaphor only once of “an invisible hand” in Wealth Of Nations (book IV).
His
juxtaposition of the assertion that “The invisible hand is an individuals’ self
interest”, supposedly from Book IV ,with the statement about how one obtains
one’s dinner from the “butcher, the brewer, and the baker” in Book I, reveals
his source is from misrepresentations by modern economists and not from what
Adam Smith was writing about on self interest.
The
same erroneous linkage is made regularly by senior economists, such as David
Friedman on Lost Legacy (see Lost Legacy: June 2006; August 2011; and
etc.).
Friedman
wriggles out of his errors of linking the two passages, to his satisfaction, by
asserting the linkage is not a general statement, which denies the generality
of the claimed statement and ignores the real and rich meaning of Smith’s
paragraph about the ‘butcher, brewer and baker’. ‘Primal Rambler’ makes the
same erroneous generalization.
For
a start, if Smith had been so careless as to assert as a general statement that
“The invisible hand is an individuals’ self interest”, he would have
contradicted a great deal of his meaning in Wealth Of Nations.
First,
because Smith knew that self-interest motivated all the actions of individuals
across society, some parts of which led to unintended consequences that were
actually of negative benefit to those who were affected by such actions, such
as consumers who faced increased prices from the self-interested clamour for
tariff protection and prohibitions of imports by “merchants and manufacturers”. This would have made his political
economy self-contradictory, which is why he opposed all monopolistic behaviours
that consequentially led to restricting competition among suppliers and the
narrowing of markets. And these were certainly not examples of an “invisible hand” channeling “self-interest”
into “socially desireable ends”.
They
are examples of “self-interest” leading to undesireable consequences, and once
we have exceptions to general statements, they are no longer true. Hence, the
assertion of Primal Rambler that by his use of the IH metaphor Smith meant
self-interest is false. In fact, Smith never linked self-interest to the IH
metaphor, or to markets, or to price theory, and so on. Moreover in the circumstances of the 18th-century
where he did use in Book IV, it was hardly about “competitive markets”.
Second,
the “butcher, brewer, and baker” example was not about an individual’s
self-interest in isolation; it described the appropriate conduct of
negotiations between the self-interested readers and the self-interested
suppliers of their meat, drink and bread for their dinners through the mutual
mediation of their individual self-interests. The jointly agreed price of the
items for one’s dinner was summarised by Smith:
“But man has almost constant occasion
for the help of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to expect it from their
benevolence only. He will be more likely to prevail if he can interest their
self–love in his favour, and shew them that it is for their own advantage to do
for him what he requires of them. Whoever offers to another a bargain of any
kind, proposes to do this. Give me that which I want, and you shall have this
which you want, is the meaning of every such offer; and it is in this manner
that we obtain from one another the far greater part of those good offices
which we stand in need of. It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the
brewer, or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their
own interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity but to their self–love,
and never talk to them of our own necessities but of their advantages” ((Book 1, chapter 2, paragraph
2).
The
absolute mediation of self-interest is clearly stated in that paragraph. Yes, self-interest draws the butcher,
brewer, and baker to labour to produce items for sale in the market, and
self-interest draws potential customers to visit the market in search of the
ingredients for their dinners, as commonly found in the 18th
century. But one’s self-interest
does not determine the price of those ingredients, because both buyers and sellers
have views on what that agreed single price should be. Smith advised readers to “address”
themselves not to the seller’s humanity, but to their “self-love and never talk to them of our own necessities
but of their advantages” in setting a price acceptable to buyers. Those engaged in commercial
negotiations will recognize the validity of Smith’s observations.
If prices were solely decided by sellers, and buyers had to accept the
sellers’ prices, the self-interests of sellers would drive prices above
competitive prices towards extortionate monopoly prices. This too definitely would not be a case
of self-interest channeling
prices “into socially desireable ends”.
It is usually at this point that modern economists try
to corer the cracks in their generalisation of self-interests driving “socially
desirable” ends, by claiming they are only talking of “competitive”
situations, not the commonplace markets that have always existed. But exceptions show the assertion is
erroneous as written, especially by ideologues and mis- interpretations of the “butcher,
brewer, baker” example.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home