My comments on Murray Rothbard's Criticism of Adam Smith
This week's posts on Libertarians reminded me of a criticial assessments I made in 2005 when I started the Lost Legacy Blog. Looking back I eventually found the post - rather long I am afraid - but it may be of interest. I have left it as I wrote it, though I noted some minor changes I would make if I wrote it today. I never took Murray Rothbard's style of debate with critics. I am told by some academic economists who knew him that Rothbard was quite abrasive and tended to bully the reputation of those who doubted his ideas.
Well, while such tittle tattle is in n way decisive, I do know with confidence that he was wrong about Adam Smith's contributions on the topic mentioned in my post.
Let me know what you think.
“Murray
Rothbard’s Myth about Adam Smith” HERE
Murray N. Rothbard,
the late and distinguished contributor to the von Mises’ school of Austrian
economics, wrote a chapter (‘The
Myth of Adam Smith’) in An Austrian Perspective on the History of Economic Thought,[1]
and a large extract from it was published in January 2006 on the Ludwig von
Mises’ Institute’s Blog.[2] During January and March I wrote six pieces
criticising Rothbard’s assertions, reproduced here with minor editorial
corrections.[3]
1
In, if I may say
so, an appropriate Rothbardian fashion (no prisoners, no ambiguity, no wasted
prose), the von Mises Institute announced its re-publication of Rothbard’s
classic in a blurb typical of Rothbard’s pugilistic style:
“In an essay that made his masterpiece
on the history of thought famous, Murray Rothbard argues that Adam
Smith's should not be called the founder of economics, nor a theorist who
improved on economic science, nor even a consistent defender of the market
economy. Rothbard sees him as unoriginal, confused, opportunistic, vastly
overrated, and even dishonest. Yet this except is only a tiny bit of what you
will find in this 2-volume wonder”.
I have read, so far, a few of
Rothbard’s contributions (I am working my way through von Mises’ “Human Action”[4] amidst other
duties[5]) and should not comment at this time on Austrian economics in general
until I am familiar with the Austrian approach, which strikes me, from recent
acquaintance with the Mises Institute Blog, as formidable, at least in its
certitudes about everything. However, I am familiar with the life and
works of Adam Smith and spend a deal of time correcting obvious errors
broadcast about him. To that extent I agree that there are many myths about the
man, his writings and his ideas, and I title this critical essay on Rothbard’s
‘The Myth of Adam Smith’ as ‘Murray
Rothbard’s Myths about Adam Smith’.
Given the length of
Murray Rothbard’s slamming critique[6], I cannot reply to it in the detail it
requires in a single Blog contribution and I shall return to other aspects of
Rothbard’s essay in future Blogs. While Murray Rothbard (1925-1995) cannot
reply, nor can Adam Smith (1723-90), but I am sure we can conduct critical
discussion without lacking in manners.
My first point of detail concerns
Rothbard’s reference to “Sir James Steuart's (1712-80) outdated two-volume
work, Principles of Political Œconomy
(1767).” Rothbard treats Smith’s neglect to mention in “Wealth of Nations”, Sir
James Steuart’s then recently published book as evidence of something underhand
and suspicious (so did Salim Rashid)[7], both hinting that Smith’s neglect was
responsible, somehow, for Steuart’s book not doing as well as it might have
done. I quote from Rothbard:
“… Sir
James Steuart's (1712-80) outdated two-volume work, Principles of Political
Oeconomy (1767). Steuart, a Jacobite who had been involved in Bonnie Prince
Charlie's rebellion, was for much of his life an exile in Germany, where he
became imbued with the methodology and ideals of German 'cameralism.'
Cameralism was a virulent form of absolutist mercantilism that flourished in
Germany in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Cameralists, even more
than western European mercantilists, were not economists at all—that is, they
did not analyse the processes of the market but were technical advisers to
rulers on how and in what way to build up state power over the economy.
Steuart's Principles was in that tradition, scarcely economics but rather a
call for massive government intervention and totalitarian planning, from
detailed regulation of trade to a system of compulsory cartels to inflationary
monetary policy.
“Even though
Steuart's Principles was out of step with the emerging classical liberal
Zeitgeist, it was no foregone conclusion that the work would have little or no
influence. The book was well received, highly respected, and sold very well,
and five years after its publication, in 1772, Steuart won out over Adam Smith
in acquiring a post as monetary consultant to the East India Company.”
Adam Smith was not a
Jacobite. His father had a credible record of commitment to the Hanoverian
King’s cause and was an active party to the Unionist shenanigans that led to
the merger of the parliaments of Scotland with England in 1707 (the Crowns were
unified in 1603). Yet Smith was not a person who carried political differences
into personal relationships.
His first published
writing was his preface to the publication of William Hamilton’s Poems on Several Occasions in 1748.
Hamilton was a Jacobite in exile, who was pardoned later. So, Smith had
no personal or political reason to ostracise Steuart or his book. Indeed, we
know he regularly conversed with him after his discreet return from exile in
1763, when Smith returned from his Tour of France in 1766. As Smith directed
some of his polemics against mercantile political economy in “Wealth of
Nations” to confute Steuart’s ‘false principles’, he hardly ignored Steuart’s
book, though he admitted, proudly, that he did this ‘without mentioning’
Steuart or his book:
“I have the
same opinion of Sir James Stewarts Book that you have. Without once mentioning
it, I flatter myself that every principle in it, will meet with a clear and
distinct confutation in mine.”[8]
I cannot think of
many, if any, occasions in which Smith criticised a living person’s writings by
name, though he could be robust with the named writings of those who were dead.
It may have had something to do with an old fashioned sense of the proprieties
common among gentlemen in 18th-century Scotland. It was quite common in
published works, well into the 19th century, for authors to refer to people’s
names with most letters blanked out. For example, James Steuart would have been
referred to as: ‘J-------------t’.
Given Steuart’s theme in favour of
mercantile-state building, I consider its failure as a book after 1772 had more
to do with its contents than to any sales it might have received if Smith had
identified it in 1776. It took some time before “Wealth of Nations” made
significant sales (a point mocked at by Rashid). From what I know of the
various editions of Smith’s book they did not sell like hot cakes (he sent free
copies to many important people) and I would wager they made greater sales in
later editions in the 19th and 20th centuries than they did while he was alive.
Frederick List[9] lambasted Smith’s “Wealth
of Nations” because it contained vigorous criticism of mercantile state
building, which List saw as the foundation for German unification and nationalism.
The consequences were seen in the 20th Century.
Rothbard takes a side-swipe at
Smith with gratuitously tendentious implications:
“in 1772, Steuart won out over Adam Smith in
acquiring a post as monetary consultant to the East India Company.”
This suggests that
Smith had applied for a post with the East India Company in competition with
Sir James Steuart and had lost the contest because Steuart was judged the
better monetary specialist. It could only convince someone who has no idea of
the facts.
For one thing, Steuart’s book circulated from 1767 and Smith did
not publish “Wealth of Nations”
until 1776. For another, the facts of the circumstances surrounding Smith’s
name lying before directors of the East India Company, who were looking for a
specialist to advise them on the currency problem they had in Bengal, rubbish
Rothbard’s unworthy implications. Smith did not apply for the post, as is clear
in his polite remarks to the person who had put his name forward without
consulting Smith first:
“I think
myself very much honoured and obliged to you for having mentioned me to the
east India Directors as a person who could be of any use to them. You have
acted in your old way of doing your friends a good office behind their backs,
pretty much as other people do them a bad one. There is no labour of any kind
which you can impose on me which I will not readily undertake. By what Mr
Stewart and Mr Ferguson hinted to me concerning your notion of the proper
remedy for the disorders of the coin in Bengal, I believe our opinions upon
that subject are perfectly the same”[10]
‘Mr Ferguson’ was
Adam Ferguson, and Smith’s spelling of Steuart’s name is how the name was spelt
in Scotland, whereas ‘Steuart’ or, more commonly ‘Stuart’, is the English
spelling.
And while discussing Rothbard’s ‘side-swipe’, I should mention the
fact that so-called ‘Bonnie Prince Charlie’ was neither ‘bonnie’ (check his
portrait!) nor a ‘Prince’. He was the foreign-speaking grandson of the former
British King, who had been deposed by constitutional means from the throne in
favour of the Hanoverian King William of Orange. Charlie’s' father was a
Pretender to the throne; his son’s claim to be a Prince was false (‘treason
never prospers, because if it prospers none dare call it treason’). To describe
Steuart as being ‘involved’ in Charlie’s futile rebellion understates his role
for he was his private secretary, suggesting a more wholesome commitment to the
Jacobite cause than merely being ‘involved’ in it; many thousands were
‘involved’ in the rebellion, but few became ‘private secretary’ to its leader.
2
The early chapters
of “Wealth of Nations” often irritate those in a hurry to read it like a modern
economics textbook. For example, Francis
Horner (1801) dismissed the significance of the early chapters:
“This
is a very superficial and unnecessary chapter; all that is valuable in the
doctrine of it stated in a single sentence. The disquisition belongs rather to
philosophy of the mind rather than to political economy: and as a metaphysical
investigation, it is treated in a very slight and unsatisfying manner”[11]
Two centuries later,
Murray Rothbard, under cover of
Schumpeter’s prodigious authority, dismisses them too. It is Rothbard’s
sweeping opinion that for no “economist before or since did the division of labour
assume such a position of commanding importance.” To the extent that this is
true it reflects more on the unfortunate neglect by such economists than any
obsession Smith may have entertained about the division of labour.
Rothbard
considers the division of labour of trifling importance compared to the
exaggerated ‘undue’ and ‘commanding importance’ accorded to it by Smith. This
is a clear difference of opinion, not open to resolution. However, Rothbard
goes much further and throws about other, more serious, charges against Smith.
Beyond the crimes of exaggeration, Rothbard adds those of downplaying the
importance of ‘capital accumulation and the growth of technological knowledge’;
not ‘apply[ing] his analysis of the division of labour to international trade;
having ‘no inkling of the Industrial Revolution going on all about him’;
plagiarizing the example of the pin factory from the French Encyclopédie (1755) and shifting ‘the
main focus’ of the importance of the division of labour ‘from mutual benefit to
an alleged irrational and innate 'propensity to truck, barter and exchange', as
if human beings were lemmings determined by forces external to their own chosen
purposes.’
After such a devastating broadside from a major post-war figure in
Austrian economics, supported by the authority of Schumpeter, a veritable giant
of the profession, it may be thought that Rothbard’s abusive rhetoric, mustered
in his intemperate chapter, was perfectly justified. I think our American
cousins call it ‘Slam Dunk’. But when reading well-known sources, we should
ignore the rhetoric and check the solidity of the assertions.
This takes us
to the core of the significance of the division or labour for Smith. He was not
writing a ‘Principles of Political Economy’ textbook, nor even a Treatise on a
topic of an aspect of political economy (currency, trade or agriculture,
etc.,), or a set of lectures for a moral philosophy class. “An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the
Wealth of Nations” was the report of his answer to the question embodied
in its title. Elsewhere,[12] I have called it a ‘one-man Royal Commission’,
after the procedure in Britain, by which a government appoints independent
worthies to enquire into a subject of importance (the causes of crime, bad
housing, transport, genetically modified foods, drug addiction, and such like)
and then publishes their findings a few years later. “Wealth of Nations” should be read with that image in mind.
It
is appropriate that Smith opens his report by taking a long view into the
evolutionary history of factors bound up with the causes of the wealth of
nations. Smith was aware that outside the perimeter of European societies there
were very different societies elsewhere on Earth, some with ancient
civilisations (India, China) and others commonly referred to as examples of the
lives of the ‘Brutes’, or the kind of ‘savage’ societies that once were
considered to have been the norm for all humans (e.g., Locke’s assertion in
1690 that in the ‘beginning all the world was America’).[13]
That he leant
heavily on the division of labour as a primary cause of the differences between
the savage societies in America and Africa, and the civilised present of
Western Europe is justifiable. That he was wrong in details and he knew nothing
of the hundreds of thousands of years of the human and proto-human societies as
they had evolved, is readily conceded, but other disciplines could now show
those economists, who hasten past these insights, quite fundamental gaps in
their understanding of human behaviour, of which subject they (including the
Austrians) claim a unique sovereignty.
In “Adam Smith’s Lost Legacy”, I
criticise the extent to which Smith’s name has become ‘practically synonymous’
with the division of labour and the extent of the market, and I try to ‘lay
this myth to rest’.[14] That he ignored others who had discussed the division
of labour is not entirely supported by thee vidence of his text. In “Wealth of
Nations”,[15] he draws attention to previous views on the division of labour.
He gives clear evidence of others before himself, presumably in the pamphlet
literature that he does not bother to cite in detail, expressing their views on
the division of labour before he did:
‘[The division of labour] is commonly supposed to be carried
furthest in some very trifling’ manufactures’ and he continues in this theme to
identify ‘great manufacturers’ that cannot collect all of their workmen into
‘the same workhouse’ in a single place (large workplaces were rare in mid-18th
century Scotland, excluding mines), and they necessarily disperse them such
that the work is ‘divided into a greater number of parts’ and ‘the division [of
labour] is not near so obvious, and has accordingly been much less observed’,[16] but that he acknowledged that it
was observed by others (from the words in my italics) is certain.
Smith
introduces the ‘pin maker’, but note (read carefully!) he writes that the
division of labour in the ‘very trifling manufacture’ of pins ‘has been very often taken notice of’
(my italics). Again Smith makes no claim to precedence or pretence at originality,
contrary to Rothbard’s assertions. The tense of ‘has been very often taken
notice of’ is clear: the ‘notice’ that others took of the division of labour
was in the past, i.e., before “Wealth of Nations” (1776); the Encyclopédie was
published in 1755, 21 years earlier, and its contents were widely known to
contemporaries interested in political economy (Smith had copies in his
library).[17]
Smith taught the division of labour since he arrived at Glasgow
College (1751) and it was also expounded by Francis Hutcheson while Smith was a
student (1737-40), and by Plato, William Petty (1683) and many others.[18]
Acknowledging observations by others, which were well known to his readers, is
hardly grounds to accuse him of plagiarism two hundred years later. In
the interim, the pamphlet literature, about which Rothbard and Rashid make a
great deal of fuss, was not treated as seriously as it is today by scholars
with Internet access to libraries that store copies.
Rothbard makes an
extraordinary assertion:
“The older
and truer perception of the motive power for specialization and exchange was
simply that each party to an exchange (which is necessarily two-party and
two-commodity) benefits (or at least expects to benefit) from the exchange;
otherwise the trade would not take place. But Smith unfortunately shifts the
main focus from mutual benefit to an alleged irrational and innate 'propensity
to truck, barter and exchange', as if human beings were lemmings determined by
forces external to their own chosen purposes.”
That it is older is
agreed, that it is truer is problematical. ‘Specialisation and exchange’
narrows the domain of the division of labour considerably unless Rothbard
insists that the division of labour was confined only to the era of commercial
exchange. The division of labour reached its modern fruition in the modern era
of commerce, but it had a long history through the four ages of man, from the
gathering-scavenging-hunting first stage onwards. Co-operation, an essential
ingredient in the division of labour, evolved through the millennia in late
proto-human (hominid) society; it did not just appear suddenly and fully
operational in early acts of exchange in human society.
Co-operation in the
scavenging or hunting of large game (larger than adult men) required more than
one common set of attributes. Age separated man’s universal talents; the young
ran faster, had strength and seldom lacked the impetuousness that often passes
for courage; the older, perhaps lamer, certainly slower than the young, and
nursing that experience that often passes for guile, fulfilled different roles.
These were not necessarily solely innate differences; they were the product of
many incidents over their life-times, learned from the accidents of experience
and observation.
In an environment where violent predators competed for the
same food sources, a division of labour amongst humans had reproductive
advantages suitable to drive social evolution (a far faster form of evolution
compared to natural selection). Scavenging and hunting big game was dangerous
work for puny humans. While multi-tasking was possible and such activities
guided by superior intelligence gave humans a competitive edge. Tracking and
locating prey (already dead or suitable for killing), trapping and stripping
the kill or the abandoned carcass quickly before rival predators, determined an
able to kill anything in their way, challenged them for possession, and
withdrawing intact, required knappers of stone tools, butchers and carriers,
plus noisy skirmishers to keep predators at bay long enough for the others to
complete their work. The nature of such work required a nascent division of
labour, some elementary forms of organisation and social cohesion.
Combined in a group
there were many reproductive and survival advantages in divisions of labour
from innate and life-cycle differences. That Smith asserts the absence of
innate differences between porters and philosophers is the result, ‘not so much
from nature, as from habit, custom, and education’ is an error regarding the
relative importance of nature versus nurture as root causes. If he insisted
that the differences were solely and absolutely caused by ‘habit, custom and
education’, he was wrong.[19] That we know differently today (though in some
quarters it is still controversial) is a result of two hundred years additional
research, and is commendable (education?), but hardly a decisive dismissal of
Smith’s complicity in common enough errors of his time and afterwards. (I wish
I could feel so certain of everything I assert as Murray Rothbard's
self-confidence in everything he asserted.)
What is important is Smith’s
denial that the division of labour was ‘derived’ from ‘the effect of any human
wisdom, which foresees and intends that general opulence to which it gives
occasion’.[20] He says much the same thing in relation to the origins and
evolution of language.[21] He went on to argue that much the same process is
behind the evolution of markets and their workings, though he obfuscated how
markets work from introducing Shakespeare’s metaphor of the invisible hand,[22]
clouding his clarity of how markets work with the unfortunate interpretation of
those (the majority?) who came to see markets as ‘miraculous’ and mysterious,
even though Smith’s single use of the metaphor in “Wealth of Nations” appears in a passage not directly related to
markets.[23]
Only much later in the evolution of the division of labour into
the creation of wealth (goods created by human toil), when the divisions of
labour had spread through co-operation, did it lead towards ‘truck, barter and
exchange [of] one thing for another’. Extended families and small bands
created their future histories in the empty wildernesses of the Earth, as their
descendants migrated through adjacent territories and then continents, and
proliferated into regular contact with other descendants from Africa. It was
contact amongst long separated human bands that drove social evolution into
exchange relationships (and the ever present phenomenon of violent plunder).[24]
Here
Rothbard separates himself from Smith’s view of the essential attribute of
human exchange. He confuses motive with means; he makes the mistake he accuses
Smith of committing. He writes:
“simply
that each party to an exchange (which is necessarily two-party and
two-commodity) benefits (or at least expects to benefit) from the exchange;
otherwise the trade would not take place.”
Yes, but, though each party
unambiguously “benefits from the exchange”, where did the only practice that
could realise the mutual benefits of trading come from, and, as important, how
does exchange take place without what Smith calls the propensity for
bargaining? Is Rothbard suggesting that it came exogenously “as if human beings
were lemmings determined by forces external to their own chosen purposes”?
Surely not! It must have come from their attempts to realise those tentative
benefits, which Smith suggested was the mechanism for trade – the behaviour
that makes it happen:
‘the necessary, though very slow and gradual consequence
of a certain propensity in human nature which has no such extensive utility;
the propensity to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another’.[25]
Concentrate on the words:
‘very slow and gradual consequence of a certain propensity’. This is Smith’s
evolutionary social model. It was not a result of a rational decision to
exchange, which everybody adopted simultaneously after reading von Mises and
Rothbard in the mid-20th century; humans discovered the alternatives (plunder
or trade) to acquiring wealth they had not created themselves through an
evident propensity that was one of the ‘original principles in human nature of
which no further account can be given’. The behaviours of our ancient predecessors
did not fossilise and no trace of how they behaved or what they thought
remains.
Smith’s other option
for the origins of the propensity are ‘the necessary consequence of the
faculties of reason and speech’[26]. In short, he did not know for certain
which option it might have been, or if there was a third option (by rational
deduction in the Austrian tradition). He did not state that ‘irrational’
propensity was definitely ‘innate’; he did not know for sure and he left the
two alternatives for future scholarship.
Two centuries later,
Rothbard asserts he knows the answer for certain. And how does he know for
certain? Because he thought it through rationally and with the benefit of two
hundred years of modern scholarship that is held in vast libraries, none of
which was available to Adam Smith in Kirkcaldy in 1766, when he wrote the
opening chapters of “Wealth of Nations”.
The alternative to bargaining for the
benefits was/is violent plunder, which no doubt many tried instead, some
‘winning’ and as many ‘losing’ (the plunderers were out plundered by their
supposed victims). Trading behaviour has always been a ‘propensity’, not a
mandate. Where non-zero sum trade happens it raises the wealth of its
participants, whereas plunder raises the wealth of the ‘winning’ party, net of
its real costs – dead and wounded, and the ever present threat from surviving
remnants of the ‘losers’ - which reduces or eliminates potential benefits from
one-way violent zero-sum transactions.
Trade does not just take place. It has
to be negotiated. It is both a process and an outcome. The parties have to
‘persuade’ each other to transact.[27] The fact that mainstream economics
ignores Smith’s ‘propensity to truck, barter and exchange’ (negotiation) as the
fundamental characteristic of trade, is a criticism of economists (including
the Austrian variety), not Adam
Smith.
3
Murray Rothbard
asserts the following unfair criticism plus an elementary error:
“In addition, Smith failed to apply his
analysis of the division of labour to international trade, where it would have
provided powerful ammunition for his own free trade policies. It was to be left
to James Mill to make such an application in his excellent theory of
comparative advantage. Furthermore, domestically, Smith placed far too much
importance on the division of labour within a factory or industry, while
neglecting the more significant division of labour among industries.”
This
is not central to my replies to Rothbard on Smith, but it typifies his
rhetoric, that he counts as a ‘failing’ in a predecessor, that another
political economist 50 or more years after he died, had ‘been left’(?) to apply
a theory which his predecessor had not created on his own account. That John
Stuart Mill elaborated on a concept on the back of David Ricardo’s work is
highly commendable (that is how science progresses and evolves), but if we are
to blame all predecessors for not anticipating our insights in the centuries
that follow them (and us!) we would have a pretty jaundiced view of the
practice of science.
But look closely at the main charge against Smith.
Rothbard asserts he ignored the division of labour in ‘international trade’ and
‘the more significant division of labour among industries.’ What breathtaking
forgetfulness on Rothbard’s part – it cannot possibly be caused by Rothbard’s
ignorance, for his reputation as a major scholar in economic science is widely
appreciated.
But to the facts. The
famous ‘pin factory’ (of which more later) was not the sole reference to the
division of labour in “Wealth of
Nations”. It was only one ‘trifling’ paragraph example, chosen I suspect
to illustrate the principle of the division of labour and not to exhaust
it.[28]
In the very next paragraph Smith writes:
“In every other art and manufacture, the effects of the division of
labour are similar to what they are in this very trifling one… The division of
labour, however, so far as it can be introduced, occasions, in every art, a
proportionable increase of the productive powers of labour. The separation of
the different trades and employments from one another, seems to have taken
place, in consequence of this advantage. This separation too is generally carried
furthest in those countries which enjoy the highest degree of industry and
improvement; what is the work of one man, in a rude state of society, being
generally that of several in an improved one…. The labour too which necessary
to produce any one complete manufacture, is almost always divided among a great
number of hands. How many different trades are employed in each branch of the
linen and woollen manufactures, from the growers of the flax and the wool, to
the bleachers and smoothers of the linen, to the dyers and dressers of the
cloth!” [29]
For Smith his survey of the application of the division of
labour in mid-18th century Scotland, and what we now know, but nobody did at
the time, was only the beginning of a deepening of commerce and industry on a
scale unprecedented in all of history that has not stopped yet, concerned the
‘downstream’ processes of product groups (flax and wool) because these were the
most evident examples of the division of labour at work in Smith's day. He did
not ‘neglect’ the significance of the division of labour ‘among’ industries at
all. He wrote about them!
Only seven
paragraphs on[30] Smith develops his lesser known (at least to those who rely
on abridgements and third-hand accounts of what Smith wrote, a charge nobody
could make against Rothbard) example of the division of labour, that of the
manufacture of the ‘accommodation’ of the ‘common artificer’, which utilises a
‘number of people’ different industries who contribute ‘a part’ to procurements
of the common labourer. These people must ‘join their different arts in order
to complete even this homely production’, writes Smith, and goes on to
elaborate on the different industries ‘in distant parts of the country’ and ‘a
great multitude of workmen’ needed to produce by their ‘joint labour’ the
common labourer’s woollen coat.
These different industries, according to
Rothbard neglected by Smith, include shepherds, weavers, fullers, ‘many
merchants and carriers’, commerce and navigation, ship-builders, sailors,
sail-makers, rope makers, drugs for dyers (‘from the remotest corners of the
world’, introducing an international trade element into his discourse, which
Rothbard calls Smith’s ‘failing’), tool-makers, makers of ‘complicated
machinery’ for ships, millers, and looms, even the ‘shears’ that ‘clip the
wool’, miners of coal and ore, builders of furnaces for smelting, timber
fellers, charcoal burners, brick-makers,, brick-layers, furnace men,
mill-wrights, forgers, smiths, all ‘joined in their different arts in order to
produce them’.
Smith, having mentioned the common labourers' other
requirements in dress, furniture, shirts, shoes, bed, kitchen grate, tables,
furniture, knives and forks, earthen and pewter plates, bread, beer, and glass
windows, concludes:
“If we examine, I say, all these things, and
consider the variety of labour employed about each of them, we shall be
sensible that without the assistance and co-operation of many thousands, the
very meanest person in a civilised country could not be provided, even
according to, what we very falsely imagine, the easy and simple manner in which
he is commonly accommodated”.[31]
4
To conclude the
discussion on Smith’s alleged plagiarism of the division of labour I shall turn
to Murray Rothbard’s own myths.
He convinced himself that he had found a ‘smoking gun’ in Smith’s version of
the division of labour and his quarrel with Adam Ferguson.
Closer analysis
shows Rothbard quiet wrong in his borrowed interpretation from Professor
Hamowy’s 'Adam Smith, Adam Ferguson, and the Division of Labour' :[32]
“Professor Hamowy has shown that Smith did not
break with his old friend, as had previously been thought, because of
Ferguson's use of the concept of the division of labour in his “Essay on
the History of Civil Society” in 1767.
In view of all the writers who had employed the concept earlier, this behaviour
would have been ludicrous, even for Adam Smith. Hamowy conjectures that the
break came in the early 1 780s, because of Ferguson's discussion at their club
of what would later be published as part of his Principles of Moral and
Political Science in 1792….
Thus Adam
Smith broke up a long-standing friendship by unjustly accusing Adam Ferguson
of plagiarizing an example which, in truth, both men had taken without
acknowledgement from the French Encyclopédie.”
Believing that such
behaviour would have been ‘ludicrous’ on Smith’s part should have been followed
by Rothbard exercising caution in copying these attributions from Professor
Hamowys. I agree that their dispute was not over the principle of the division
of labour, because of well-known common knowledge of their prior publication in
more ancient writings, as Smith acknowledges in his reference to the pin
manufactory example.[33]
But what were their differences about then? Ferguson
in his History of Civic Society
(1767) introduced the relatively new proposition of the division of labour
causing what we now call ‘alienation’, a theme taken up by Smith in ‘Wealth of Nations’.[34] If there was
to be a quarrel over precedence it was more likely to be the subject of
alienation and not the principle of the division of labour. Ferguson’s
references to alienation pre-date ‘Wealth
of Nations’, but they do not pre-date his ‘Lectures in Jurisprudence’ delivered between 1750 and 1764.[35]
The
fact that Smith's lecturers were not published until the end of the 19th
century does not disqualify a quarrel over precedence in alienation because
several hundred persons heard his lectures, he spoke about his ideas regularly
in his clubs and ‘social hours’, and Ferguson mixed in the same circles. The
‘lost’ lectures misled Karl Marx into attributing to Ferguson precedence in
‘alienation’ theory, and describing him as the ‘teacher’ of Adam Smith and also
Smith as his ‘pupil’![36] But Smith had lectured in 1763[37] on alienation
years before Ferguson published his version in 1767.
But was it really a
quarrel, as Professor Hamowys claims and Rothbard endorses, about the contents
of a book Ferguson was to publish in 1792 (Smith died in 1790), or was it about
something else published earlier while Smith was alive? In the original report
of the alleged charges by Smith he is alleged to have accused Ferguson:
‘of
having borrowed some of his inventions without owning them. This Ferguson
denied, but owned he had derived many notions from a French author, and that
Smith had been there before him’[38]
It was not just a
‘French source’ in the original quotation, but a ‘French Author’, and the best
candidate for the French author is Baron Montesquieu and his book, ‘Spirit of the Law’ (1748), whose
concepts and ideas featured strongly in Smith’s lectures at Glasgow University,
which we know because he acknowledged Montesquieu six times (though not a
further 20 times). Speech does not lend itself to author citations and, anyway,
Smith never edited the students’ notes for accuracy, and his own manuscript for
Jurisprudence was burned on his
instructions a short while before he died. His lectures were taken down by
students and widely circulated – two copies of which were discovered over 100
years later. Ferguson could not have quoting from this source
directly, but he could have been quoting from another set of student notes (now
lost) or, more likely from student’s reports of Smith’s lectures circulating in
the Edinburgh clubs.
Ferguson’s History
of Civil Society appeared in 1767 and in its first edition he made no
acknowledgement of Montesquieu’s work as a source, and Smith would have
recognised this deficiency. Indeed, Ferguson published the following bizarre
apology in the second 1773 edition:
‘In
his [Montesquieu’s] writings will be found, not only the original of what I am
now, for the sake of order, to copy from him, but likewise probably the source
of many observations, which in different places, I may, under the belief of
invention, have repeated without quoting the author.’
This leaves me to
deal with the final and, if I may opine, gratuitously false criticism of Smith
on trivial arithmetical details (which Rothbard also manages to get wrong!) of
the famous pin manufactory example in ‘Wealth
of Nations’:
‘There is strong
evidence that the 'French source' for both writers was the article on Epingles
(pins) in the Encyclopédie (1755), since that article mentions 18 distinct
operations in making a pin, the same number repeated by Smith in the Wealth of
Nations, although in English pin factories 25 was the more common number of
operations.’
What are we to make of this ‘evidence’? Is Rothbard
arguing that the alleged discrepancy between 18 (Encyclopédie) and 25 (England)
shows he had caught out Smith in a borrowed example? A closer reading of the
passage in ‘Wealth of Nations’ suggests otherwise.
First of all the ‘18’
operations are reported to have been ‘very often taken notice of’ (p.14), i.e.,
sufficiently familiar to be common knowledge by 1776 (21 years after the Encyclopédie article in 1755). Then
Smith goes on to describe a ‘small pin manufactory, which he states
emphatically: ‘I have seen’[39] and Rothbard questions the veracity of this
statement and, by implication, adds to his charges that Smith was also a liar.
However, Smith’s actual statement says that he saw:
“a small manufactory of
this kind where ten men only were employed, and where some of them consequently
performed two or three distinct operations. But though they were very poor, and
therefore but indifferently accommodated with the necessary machinery, they
could when they exerted themselves, make among them about twelve pounds of pins
in a day. There are in a pound upwards of four thousand pins of a middling
size. Those ten persons, therefore, could make among them upwards of
forty-eight thousand pins in a day. Each person, therefore, making a tenth part
of forty-eight thousand pins, might be considered as making four thousand eight
hundred pins a day. But if they had all wrought separately and independently,
and without any of them having been educated to this peculiar business, they
certainly could not each of them have made twenty, perhaps not one pin in day;
that is, certainly not the two hundred and fortieth, perhaps not four thousand
eight hundred part of what they are at present capable of performing, in
consequences of a proper division and combination of their different
operations”.[40]
The pin manufactory
Smith describes in detail does not include anything about how many operations
are involved, other than that among the ten men ‘some of them consequently
performed two or three distinct operations.’ The ‘18’ operations cited by
Rothbard as ‘evidence’ comes from an earlier sentence in the paragraph!
So
what is Rothbard’s ‘evidence’ for his gratuitous and false implication that
there was something untoward in Smith’s account of what he saw? Rothbard’s
assertion is that ‘the same number [18] is repeated by Smith in the 'Wealth of
Nations’ which shows he claims that he has caught Smith out, because ‘in
English pin factories 25 was the more common number of operations’.
Unfortunately,
Rothbard didn’t catch out anybody but himself in his (careless) misreading of
Adam Smith, and, er, by the way, I note that Rothbard gave no citation for this
statement about ‘25’ operations being more common in ‘England’. Smith,
incidentally, lived in Scotland and Rothbard, like many North Americans, made
the usual, and somewhat irritating, mistake of talking about ‘England’, one of
the four nations making-up the United Kingdom, as if what happened in ‘England’
was synonymous with what happened in Scotland and that Smith should have known
about pin factories south of the border, in days, remember, when Edinburgh to
London took a six-day coach journey.
It is possible that Rothbard did not
read Chapter 1 in “Wealth of Nations” with enough care (though he describes it
has the book’s most ‘famous’ paragraph!) in pursuit of his intemperate
accusation Smith’s falsehoods. His normal standards of scholarly accuracy on
this occasion had slipped
severely.
5
Murray Rothbard
pounces of Adam Smith at the end of his extract on the differences between
‘productive’ and ‘unproductive labour’ and completely misses the point, as so
many have, including Karl Marx (that is a strange combination – Rothbard
sharing something in common with Karl Marx!).
Many people confuse
‘unproductive’ in Smith’s sense with ‘useless’ or ‘unimportant’ labour, when
Smith’s distinction had nothing to do with the merits or utility of labour.
That the Physiocrats had similar nomenclature for productive labour from their
‘produit net’ is not relevant. Smith used the distinction in a different sense.
The Physiocrats confined their meaning to products of agriculture from the
biological fact that an amount of seed when planted and grown to maturity
resulted in a physically greater amount of seeds or food. That this produit net
was visible, obvious and beyond dispute (outside droughts) was too obvious to
be contested.
Remember, Smith’s
book was a report on his ‘Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of
Nations’. It was not a textbook on political economy. It was a report on his
applications of political economy, as the subject existed in the mid-18th
century, plus whatever elements he added to his evolutionary model of man in
society from his perspectives of moral sentiments, jurisprudence, and history.
Its focus was on the wealth, the annual output of nations, but primarily
Britain, and how in each country its capacity to produce the real wealth of a
nation (and not the amount of gold, silver or paper money its citizens or its
prince hoarded) would grow year by year with efficacious policies, gradually,
continually and without direction.
An amount of raw
material did not visibly result in a net product in the same quantitative
manner – seeds bore fruit – because the physical product of raw materials was
not visible in a larger amount of something tangible. Making a saddle out of
leather, metal studs and stitching did not produce more leather. It produced a
saddle. The notion that labour added to raw material produced a higher value
and not a larger physical output required a different perspective, and if I may
suggest it, a higher level of conceptual insight, which some French économistes
approached, but the majority of Physiocrats did not. The latter treated
manufactured products as ‘sterile’.
Tracing exegetically
the origins of this conceptual insight that is now common place is not my
purpose. I shall confine my remarks to the distinction as understood by Adam
Smith.
Smith regarded
labour as productive if it contributed to growth of the net product of wealth.
It followed that labour that did not contribute to the growth of net wealth was
unproductive. That this is a narrower definition than is common place nowadays,
which now includes labour producing intangible services sold in markets, is
accepted.
Our understanding of productive labour has matured as the economy
matured from Smith’s fairly simple commercial society of a majority of farmers,
and a minority of journeymen, tradesmen, merchants and manufacturers, producing
food, clothing, shelter, household goods, implements and trinkets typical of
18th-century living standards and implements of the 18th century carrying trade
and of the implements of war. The mass consumer and service society of late
capitalism and big government was far ahead of the conceptual horizons of
Smith, his contemporaries and immediate successors. Rothbard’s penetrating 20th-century hindsight is hardly relevant when judging
what Smith should have known, anticipated or been aware of (e.g., the
‘industrial revolution’), but which, like all his contemporaries, he did not.
Smith was interested in what caused the growth of wealth. His identification
of productive labour the cause of growth, and unproductive labour as labour not
causing growth, is a simplification that was not in error for his purposes and
its time. He saw the motivational causes of labour leading to growth as the
result of the frugality of those (like journeyman manufacturers working in
small forges, blacksmith’s shops, saddlers yards and weaving sheds attached to
the labourers’ houses, and such like) whose savings from their revenues
(incomes) from productive activities were re-invested into hiring productive
labour to create tangible products to be sold in markets.
In contrast, those
he called the ‘prodigals’ spent from their revenues to hire domestic hands and
consumer goods, which did not produce output that was sold in markets. The
output labour was consumed by the persons hiring their services in the form of
domestic labour that produced a degree of comfort satisfying the hirers’ urge
to indolence and the trinkets that flattered their egos. To the extent that
people were frugal and investing their savings, the economy would grow; to the
extent that they were prodigal and spent on their consumption the economy would
grow more slowly.
That is all he meant
by labour being either productive or unproductive. It was a distinction with a
difference within terms that suited Smith’s purpose to inquire into the nature
and causes of the wealth of nations.
Rothbard concludes from his
misunderstanding:
“Clearly, Smith wanted far more investment towards future
production and less present consumption than the market was willing to choose.
One of the contradictions of this position, of course, is that accumulating
more capital goods at the expense of present consumption will eventually result
in a higher standard of living unless Smith prepared to counsel a perpetual and
accelerated shift toward more and more never-to-be-consumed means of
production.”
Again Rothbard misunderstands Smith’s approach. He did not write
a manifesto; he did not advocate, nor expect, that everybody should cease being
prodigal and convert to being frugal, and certainly not that the state should
enforce such a ludicrous proposition. He described what many people did and
what a few did differently, and what the consequences were from their
behaviours in terms of the effect of their actions on the growth in a nation’s
wealth. What people did next, as a result of understanding the differences in
the distinct behaviours, he left an open question. He always cautioned against
‘men of system’ and their fanaticism that tolerated no exceptions (a mood or
manner of behaviour, if I may say so, that would incorporate much of the
writing style of Murray Rothbard, based on the extract from his book).
Smith
noted that the frugality of income earners in contemporary 18th- century
Britain was sufficient to bring about a gradual, persistent and steady rate of
economic growth in real output (and real wages for common labourers),
sufficiently encouraging for him to believe it could offset the ‘wasteful’
expenditures (in terms of growth, not civilised comforts) on the ‘dignity of
the sovereign’ and the wars of governments. He did not advocate a kind of
‘Stalinist’ dash for growth through ‘heavy industry’ at the expense of
consumption.
He happily left to individuals the decision to spend all, or to
save some, of their revenues; implicitly, he suggested the more that
individuals chose to save out of their urge for frugality, the relatively
faster the nation’s growth rate would be, a true proposition not a falsehood.
Contrary to Rothbard’s ‘it’s either investment or consumption nightmare’ (not a
choice in the 18th century), Smith considered that there was sufficient of each
available type of labour to produce the desired outcome as a trend over time
that would enrich the wealth of the nation.
To this extent, I believe Murray
Rothbard’s critique of his version of Adam Smith’s myths is more a
demonstration of Murray Rothbard’s Myths about Adam Smith.
6
Murray Rothbard
wrote his polemic against Adam Smith entirely based on his reputation as an
Austrian economist, making charge after charge against his target without
giving the kind of detailed evidence support his case expected from a younger
economist yet to make a reputation among professionals peers.
Rothbard
apparently expected his Austrian colleagues and sympathisers (and others, such
as myself, who admire their work without necessarily subscribing sufficiently
to be an affiliate) to accept his, albeit intemperate, judgements uncritically.
However, should his readers be familiar with Adam Smith’s life and work, they
might recoil from his more extreme criticism, perhaps, as I do, by assessing
Rothbard’s detailed points (on the few occasions where he gives any), which are
clearly incorrect exegetically (as itemised in previous sections) and are bald
generalisations suitable for opinionated journalists.
In this respect,
consider Rothbard’s criticism of Adam Smith on what became known after his
death in 1790 as the ‘Industrial Revolution’.
“Smith's use of an example of a small French pin-factory rather than a
larger British one highlights a curious fact about his celebrated Wealth of
Nations: the renowned economist seems to have had no inkling of the Industrial
Revolution going on all about him. Although he was a friend of Dr John Roebuck,
the owner of the Carron iron works, whose opening in 1760 marked the beginning
of the Industrial Revolution in Scotland, Smith showed no indication that he
knew of its existence. Although he was at least an acquaintance of the great
inventor James Watt, Smith displayed no knowledge whatever of some of Watt's
leading inventions. He made no mention in his famous book of the canal boom
which had begun in the early 1760s, of the very existence of the burgeoning
cotton textile industry, or of pottery or of the new methods of making beer.
There is no reference to the enormous drop in travel costs that the new
turnpikes were bringing about.
In contrast, then, to those historians who praise Smith for his
empirical grasp of contemporary economic and industrial affairs, Adam Smith was
oblivious to the important economic events around him.”
Was Rothbard aware of the conditions in which
Smith wrote the bulk of “Wealth of Nations”, and certainly its first chapters?
He was not writing in a well-endowed University library – he left Glasgow in
January 1764. He wrote on the basis of whatever books he had acquired
privately; he did not have a tenth of the books available to Rothbard in the
last quarter of the 20th century, plus the 200 years of additional
academic research published in journal articles.
Rothbard sneers: “the renowned economist seems to have had no
inkling of the Industrial Revolution going on all about him.”
For a start,
Rothbard should have elaborated on the details of the “the Industrial
Revolution going on all about him” and identified whom among Smith’s
contemporaries had an ‘inkling’ of the Industrial Revolution in the third
quarter of the 18th century?
That Smith knew Dr John Roebuck and James Watt
is beyond doubt. That he should have grasped the significance of the Carron
Ironworks for a pending industrial revolution is extravagant. What features of
Roebuck’s investment were progenitors of the power-driven industry of the 19th
century that became known as the Industrial Revolution? Carron was certainly
large scale, but it was not power driven.
T. S. Ashton
declared that the lighting of the furnace at Carron on 26 December 1760 was the
day when the industrial revolution began,[41] but from his well-documented
hindsight, not his foresight, and the same hindsight is found in abundance
among scholars, not in 1760, but after 1860 when the contours of industrial
development taken together were visible to all who shared research-fed
hindsight from privileged vantage points, including, of course, Murray Rothbard
writing in the 1960s.
James Watt was Glasgow University’s instrument maker and
part-time dabbler in mechanics. Smith taught yards away from Watt’s workshop,
but little of Watt’s future role in the power-driven industrial revolution was
visible to Smith during 1751-1763. The early years of Watt’s experiments with
steam power were related to the pumping of water out of coal mines (an ancient
trade) and not the driving of large factory-based machinery in the next
century.
There has been a long-standing debate among economic historians about
Smith’s awareness of the isolated, separate and dispersed changes slowly
beginning to appear in the last quarter of the 18th century. I discuss this in
more detail in ‘Adam Smith’s Lost
Legacy’.[42] I conclude broadly in favour of Charles Kindleberger’s
assessment that Smith was not aware, nor had he good reason to be so, and that
R. M. Hartwell’s assessment that he was aware is wrong in detail and in his
assertions about the evidence, as were Rothbard’s assertions about Smith’s lack
of foresight.
As for Rothbard’s straws about ‘canals’, Smith discussed their
suitability for public investment; of ‘turnpike roads’ he discussed their
suitability for public or private management in “Wealth of Nations”,[43] though
there was a long way to go before they would reap large scale economies of
scale. It still took two days to travel from Glasgow to Edinburgh, a distance
of 40 miles, in the 1760s, and the state of most of Britain’s roads remained
chronic well into the 1840s. Smith recognised importance of roads, for
commercial prosperity and he discussed the advantages of better roads for
commercial transport by six-horse pulled wagons.
As with other details in
Rothbard’s polemic, while there is room for debate about the conclusions we can
draw from such details, and opinions may differ legitimately, I come back to my
main charge that Rothbard on Smith is unfair where he is wrong and dubious when
he says something with which reasonable people might be open minded. Rothbard
and his sympathisers have few grounds for his expressed absolute certainties
about Smith’s alleged myths, given that he created more than a few myths about
Adam Smith himself.
[1] Edward Elgar,
1995; Mises Institute 2006, 2-vols.
[3] The original six
Blog pieces are in the Archives (January/February, 2006) as they were written.
[4] Ludwig von
Mises, Human Action,
[5] At the time I
was writing companion web material for Strategic
Negotiation (EBS, 2006)
[6] All
references to Murray Rothbard’s chapter are from the von Mises Institute Blog,
and appear in italics (see von Mises Institute’s blog or Chapter 5 of
Rothbard’s 2-vol book
[7] Salim Rashid, The Myth of Adam Smith, 1995, which
covers similar ground and identical arguments to Rothbard, but I am not sure in
which direction the precedence flowed.
[8] Correspondence of Adam Smith: Smith
to William Pulteney, 3 September 1772, no 133, pp. 163-4, Liberty Fund,
1987
[9] List, F. “National System of Political Economy”
(1841)
[10] Correspondence of Adam Smith, Smith to
William Pulteney, 3 September 1772, no 133, p. 164, Liberty Fund, 1987
[11] Brown, V. and
Taylor, W. B. 1994. The Horner Papers,
Edinburgh University Press.
[12] Adam Smith’s Lost Legacy, Palgrave
Macmillan, p.
[13] Locke, J.
[1690] 1988. To Treatises on
Government, ed. Haslett, P. Cambridge, p. 343
[14] Adam Smith’s Lost Legacy, op cit,
chapter 26
[15] Paragraph 2,
Chapter 1 of “Wealth of Nations”
[16] WN I.i.2: p. 14
[17] Bonar, J.
[1894] 1932. A Catalogue of the
Library of Adam Smith,
[18] Plato, The Republic; Petty, W. 1683;
Hutcheson, F. 1755. A System of Moral
Philosophy;
[19] WN I.ii.4:
pp28-29
[20] WN I.ii.1: page
25
[21] Smith,
1761.Considerations Concerning the First Formation of Languages and the
Different Genius of original and compound languages’, The Philological Miscellany, May 1761, pp440-79
[22] Macbeth, 3:2
[23] WN IV.ii.9. p.
456
[24] I discuss these
themes in my (unpublished) Pre-History
of the Deal, 2000-2
[25] WN I.ii.1: page
25
[26] WN I.ii.2. p.
25
[27] Lectures in Jurisprudence, 1763,
vi.56, p. 352
[28] WN I.i.3, pages
14-15
[29] WN I.i.4: page
15
[30] WN I.i.11,
pages 22-24
[31] WN I.i.11:
pages 22-4)
[32] Economica, August 1968, p. 253
[33] “Wealth of Nations”, p. 14-15
[34] WN
V.i.f.50. pp 781-782
[35] Published in an
accessible edition by Liberty Fund in 1982
[36] Marx, K. 1867. Capital, p. 123, n.1; p. 354; pp.
361-2
[37] Lectures, LJ[B]: 329, p. 539
[38] Carlyle, A.
1860, 2nd ed. Autobiography of
Alexander Carlyle
[39] WN I.i. p.15
[40] WN I.i.3. p. 15
[41] Ashton, T. S.
1948. The Industrial revolution,
1760-1830, Oxford
[42] Adam Smith’s Lost Legacy, Chapter 29:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2005
[43] WN Book V
Murray Rothbard’s Myths about Adam Smith, Gavin Kennedy, February 2006. © Gavin Kennedy,
2006.
5 Comments:
"His normal standards of scholarly accuracy on this occasion had slipped severely."
No, this was Rothbard's usual standard of scholarly accuracy. For instance, he attacked Hegel quite viciously *without having read a single work by him*: the two citations concerning Hegel in that section of his HOT are to Popper and a Sovietologist, i.e., his entire knowledge of Hegel was from two people who were *not even Hegel scholars*, and on that basis he tore the man a new... well, you know what.
Rothbard put earlier thinkers into two categories: libertarian, or not. If you fell in the "not" category you got trashed, by whatever means possible.
Gene
Thanks for the insights.
I had heard from academics who knew him when they were at LSE. They did speak of his kindness or his proclivity for understand his critics. He may have been entirely innocent, but I formed my ideas from his remarks on Adam Smith.
Bombastic men of certainties are not ornaments of the profession.
He must have out a lot of young academics off from Libertarianism, at least how he represented it.
Gavin
Gene
Correction:
"They did NOT speak of his kindness or his proclivity for understand his critics. He may have been entirely innocent, but I formed my ideas from his remarks on Adam Smith.
Bombastic men of certainties are not ornaments of the profession."
Gavin
I agree, Rothbardès criticism of Smith is quite harsh at times, nevertheless, Smith did plagiarize by modern standards and that should not be ignored. Especially, when his borrowed and own ideas continue to impact the entire world.
"Rothbard concludes from his misunderstanding: “Clearly, Smith wanted far more investment towards future production and less present consumption than the market was willing to choose. One of the contradictions of this position, of course, is that accumulating more capital goods at the expense of present consumption will eventually result in a higher standard of living unless Smith prepared to counsel a perpetual and accelerated shift toward more and more never-to-be-consumed means of production.” Again Rothbard misunderstands Smith’s approach. He did not write a manifesto; he did not advocate, nor expect, that everybody should cease being prodigal and convert to being frugal..."
I don't think you are entirely correct here. There are normative statements in WH regarding this matter:
"Whatever, therefore, we may imagine the real wealth and revenue of a country to consist in, whether in the value of the annual produce of its land and labour, as plain reason seems to dictate; or in the quantity of the precious metals which circulate within it, as vulgar prejudices suppose; in either view of the matter, every prodigal appears to be a public enemy, and every frugal man a public benefactor."
Public enemy is quite a strong term (even insinuating criminality) and it confirms Rothbard's claim that Smith made a value judgement concerning prodigals and frugal men.
Post a Comment
<< Home