I mostly Agree With the Good Folk at Bleeding Heart Libertarians Blog
MATT ZWOLINSKI posts “Adam Smith’s Moral and Political Philosophy”
on Bleeding Heart Libertarians HERE
Samuel
Fleishacker writes a new entry (2013) in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on
“Adam Smith’s
Moral and Political Philosophy.” The whole thing is worth reading,
including the extremely helpful summary of Smith’s complicated moral theory as
developed in his Theory of Moral
Sentiments.
[GK: I very much agree:
follow the link HERE
The fifth section
on Smith’s political philosophy will be of primary interest. Fleishacker
describes Smith as an advocate of a relatively minimal state … :
The
practical point of his treatise on economics was to urge this restrained,
modest approach to economic intervention on governing officials. Smith did not
favor as hands-off an approach as some of his self-proclaimed
followers do today—he believed that states could and should re-distribute
wealth to some degree, and defend the poor and disadvantaged against those who
wield power over them in the private sector (see Fleischacker 2004, § 57)—but
he certainly wanted the state to end all policies, common in his mercantilist
day, designed to favor industry over agriculture, or some industries over
others. Smith believed strongly in the importance of local knowledge to
economic decision-making, and consequently thought that business should be left
to businesspeople, who understand the particular situations in which they work
far better than any government official (on this Hayek understood Smith well:
see Hayek 1978 Hayek, Friedrich,
1978, “Adam Smith's Message in Today's Language,” in Hayek, New Studies in Philosophy, Politics,
Economics and the History of Ideas, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, pp. 267–9] and C. Smith 2013) [Smith,
Craig, 2013, “Adam Smith and the New Right,” in The Oxford Handbook of Adam Smith, C. J. Berry, M. Paganelli
& C. Smith (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 539–558]. By the same
token, governance should be kept out of the hands of businesspeople,
since they are likely to use it to promote their particular interests, and not
be concerned for the well-being of the citizenry as a whole: Smith’s opposition
to the East India Company is based on this principle (see Muthu 2008).
Until the late eighteenth century, most writers on the role of
government vis-à-vis the poor maintained that governments should keep the poor
in poverty, so that they show proper respect to their superiors and not waste
money on drink. Smith had more influence than anyone else in changing this
attitude—he was one of the earliest and most fervent champions of the rights
and virtues of the poor, arguing against wage caps and other constraints that
kept the poor from rising socially and economically
So, given that
Smith was such a champion of the poor, why did he favor a limited government?
Why not have the government do more to help the poor? Fleishacker’s essay
contains a lengthy discussion of Smith’s answer to this question, and again,
the whole thing is worth reading:
“The
first answer to that is that Smith did not think government officials were
competent to handle much beside the needs of defense and the administration of
justice…..In addition, Smith holds that social sanctions can do a better job at
many tasks that other thinkers expected of political sanctions….Finally, Smith
limits the activities of governments because he considers it crucial to the
development of virtue that people have plenty of room to act, and shape their
feelings, on their own…Indeed, for Smith, governments can best encourage virtue
precisely by refraining from encouraging virtue.”
Smith doesn’t look
much like a contemporary libertarian. …
And if you
identify libertarianism with the strict natural-rights view of Nozick and
Rothbard, than I suppose that’s correct. … If one classifies thinkers according
to their political outputs, rather than their underlying moral inputs, then it
makes good sense to classify all all of
these people as libertarians. …
But
for purposes of the broader political conversation, we are all of us, Adam
Smith included, libertarians.”
Comment
The long quotation from Bleeding Heart Libertarians shows a Blog dominated by deep
thinkers of high integrity. It is
worth following. I do. I am on a moderate wing of
Libertarianism and sometimes feel it is necessary put clear water between
myself and other Libertarians on some issues, including a few writing for the Adam Smith
Institute (London), of which I am
a Fellow. You can certainly add
the names of Ayn Rand and Murray Rothbrd to that list. If Matt Zwolinski is willing
to include Adam Smith in the tent Libertarian Grand Tent, then I am comfortable
to be included in it too.
Do follow the links and see how comfortable you might
be too.
3 Comments:
To what extent did Burke have an influence on Smith and vice versa, if anything at all?
SM
Apologies - temporarily 'lost' your question.
Burke wrote to Smith shortly after reading TMS in praise of it. They met several times and he visited Panmure House and travelled with Smith to West Scotland.
When the repression against disturbance in the 'lower orders' occurred after 1793, Burke moved away publically from Smith's works.
Burke did not influence Smith as far as I know.
Gavin
SM
Apologies - temporarily 'lost' your question.
Burke wrote to Smith shortly after reading TMS in praise of it. They met several times and he visited Panmure House and travelled with Smith to West Scotland.
When the repression against disturbance in the 'lower orders' occurred after 1793, Burke moved away publically from Smith's works.
Burke did not influence Smith as far as I know.
Gavin
Post a Comment
<< Home