Brad Delong versus Jeff Weintraub: Two Giants in the History of Economic Thought Go Toe to Toe
Jeff Weintraub Opens a Debate with Brad Delong HERE
over "Adam Smith's
conceptual sleight-of-hand on exchange, cooperation, and the foundations of
social order"
This was a
response by Jeff Weintraub to one section of a post by Brad DeLong posing containing "the question "Exchange and its vicissitudes as fundamental to human
psychology and society?" and followed that with a justly famous quotation
from Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations. As usual, Brad's
question zeroed in on some crucial issues. I was provoked to start
writing a message about some of those issues, which I thought would run a few
lines ... but it turned out to be a little longer, so I might as well share
it." Jeff Weintraub
Nobody ever saw a
dog make a fair and deliberate exchange of one bone for another with another
dog.... When an animal wants to obtain something either of a man or of another
animal, it has no other means of persuasion but to gain the favour of those
whose service it requires. A puppy fawns upon its dam, and a spaniel endeavours
by a thousand attractions to engage the attention of its master who is at
dinner, when it wants to be fed by him. Man sometimes uses the same arts with
his brethren, and when he has no other means of engaging them to act according
to his inclinations, endeavours by every servile and fawning attention to
obtain their good will. He has not time, however, to do this upon every
occasion. In civilised society he stands at all times in need of the
cooperation and assistance of great multitudes, while his whole life is scarce
sufficient to gain the friendship of a few persons....
[M]an has almost
constant occasion for the help of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to
expect it from their benevolence only. He will be more likely to prevail if he
can interest their self-love in his favour, and show them that it is for their
own advantage to do for him what he requires of them. Whoever offers to another
a bargain of any kind, proposes to do this. Give me that which I want, and you
shall have this which you want, is the meaning of every such offer; and it is
in this manner that we obtain from one another the far greater part of those
good offices which we stand in need of. It is not from the benevolence of the
butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their
regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity but
to their self-love....
Let's start
with those dogs, since that's where the deceptive argumentation begins, and a
more careful examination of what Smith says about dogs already begins to
undermine his carefully constructed dichotomy. Sure, it's probably true
that nobody ever saw two dogs exchange bones of equivalent value. (Why
would they want to do that?) But so what? That point is just a
distraction from the real question. The central agenda of this passage is
to argue that the only two ways
to get help or assistance from someone else are (a) self-interested exchange or
(b) an appeal to their "benevolence" by begging and
"fawning". Let's forget humans for a moment. Is that
second option the only way dogs
ever do it?
Smith wants us to
think the answer is yes, but the answer is obviously no. To see why, we
should pay attention to what happens in the three sentences immediately preceding the quotation. Smith,
in effect, denies that dogs (and presumably other canines) hunt in packs. If
you think I'm making that up, go back and re-read the relevant sentences.
Two greyhounds, in
running down the same hare, have sometimes the appearance of acting in some
sort of concert. Each
turns her toward his companion, or endeavours to intercept her when his
companion turns her toward himself. This, however, is not the effect of
any contract, but of the
accidental concurrence of their passions in the same object at that particular
time. [my boldings]
No, dogs don't
trade one bone for another. But dogs and other animals definitely do cooperate (not just in pairs, but in
packs) in obtaining things they could not obtain, or achieving things they
could not achieve, as individuals. In the process of cooperation, they help
each other out. And they regularly do so in ways that do not involve market exchange (or servile
fawning).
It's probably
correct to say that two dogs pursuing a hare together haven't made a
"contract" (that would depend, in part, on precisely what Smith means
by "contract" here). But is that logically equivalent to claiming, as
Smith implies by a cunning conceptual slide, that the two dogs aren't really
acting in "concert"? A moment's reflection should be sufficient to
make the answer embarrassingly obvious.
OK, perhaps Smith
didn't know dogs that well. (Actually, I suspect that's not so, but let's
just concede the possibility.) But humans can hunt in packs, too, and do
lots of other things in packs. Humans act in concert all the time, in ways that
are not based on trucking and bartering. That may seem like an obvious fact,
once it's pointed out ... but a major purpose of Smith's discussion in the
first several pages of that chapter is to obscure the theoretical significance of this obvious fact.
Why would Smith
want to obscure that conceptual point?
We don't need to
try to read Smith's mind, but we do know that Smith is a careful analytical
system-builder and a writer of great rhetorical skill and sophistication.
(His writings on rhetoric are justly admired.) And one can't help
noticing that obscuring, or evading, that conceptual point serves a useful
function in helping Smith lay the foundations for his core theoretical argument
in WN.
As I've already
noted, Smith tries hard to convey the impression that the only significant basis for sustained
mutually beneficial interaction between individuals is self-interested exchange, which on the one side is rooted in
certain basic impulses or motivations built into human nature (self-interest +
the impulse to exchange), and on the other side gives rise (unintentionally but
intelligibly) to a dynamic system
of self-interested exchange (the market) with its own distinctive laws &
dynamics. Smith further suggests that the only possible alternative basis for (intermittent) mutual aid or beneficial
interaction is gratuitous "benevolence" or (to use a later,
19th-century, word) altruism.
But that's a false
dichotomy, since it implicitly rules out other bases for concerted action and mutually beneficial
interaction that do, indeed, play significant roles in real life.
What am I getting
at? Well, let's review the first sentence from the second paragraph you quoted:
[M]an has almost
constant occasion for the help of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to
expect it from their benevolence only.
Yes, man (or
human) does have constant needs
for coordinated action, mutually beneficial interaction, and assistance from
others. (So do wolves.) And it's true that gratuitous altruism or
"benevolence" cannot serve as the only basis for them, quite aside
from the fact that constantly wheedling other people for favors or handouts is
demeaning. But are those really the only
two alternatives? No, of course not. This is a cleverly constructed, and
rhetorically effective, false dichotomy.
Let me step back
and point out that, in the most basic analytical terms, there are at least three ways to achieve sustained
coordination of human actions (even if we just ignore "benevolence"
for the moment).
(1) One obvious
possibility is top-down command, or what we might euphemistically term
"imperative coordination" (to use Parsons's idiosyncratic and
somewhat bowdlerizing translation of Weber's Herrschaft). And in fact this mode of coordination turns up
right in Chapter 1 of Book I of WN, since that is precisely how the the
division of labor within the
famous pin factory is instituted and run. Yes, the rest of WN goes on
to show how it is possible to have an effective division of labor (i.e.,
dynamic systems of simultaneous differentiation and coordination) without the necessity for conscious
top-down coordination based on command—i.e., a division of labor can be
coordinated by the impersonal system of the self-regulating market—and that's a brilliant and profound theoretical achievement.
But we shouldn't forget that domination or authority play a role, too. And, to
repeat, the coordination of action within
Smith's pin factory (or any other formal organization) is not based, in principle, on either
gratuitous "benevolence" or
the self-interested exchange of commodities.
(Marx, of course,
hammers that point home with his analysis of the two complementary forms of the division of labor in the capitalist
mode of production, and brilliantly spells out some of the implications.)
(2) A second possible
mode of coordinating human action is through the market—i.e., an impersonal, dynamic, and
self-regulating system of self-interested
exchange. Let's be conceptually clear and precise here. Smith's point
about how the market operates as a system is that it allows tens, thousands, or
millions of people to be connected in chains of mutually beneficial interaction
without having to consciously
coordinate their actions or reach agreements about them, without having to care
about what those other people need or want, without even knowing they exist. In
so far as those millions of mutual strangers "cooperate" in the
market system, that "cooperation" is purely functional and
metaphorical. In fact, the beauty of the market is precisely that it allows for
systematic and beneficial coordination without
the need for either conscious cooperation or conscious top-down "imperative coordination" (i.e.,
domination).
(3) But that
brings us to a third possible mode of coordinating human action, which is conscious cooperation. Humans can
sometimes manage to pursue joint or common ends, not through the indirect
mechanisms of self-interested exchange of commodities, nor by simultaneously
submitting to a common superior who directs and coordinates their actions (the
Hobbesian solution), but by engaging in concerted action guided by common
agreement, custom, habituation, etc.. Not only can humans do it, even dogs and
wolves can do it—despite what Smith's second paragraph in Chapter 2 of Book I
of WN
might seem to imply.
Conscious
cooperation, by the way, is not
identical to gratuitous "benevolence" or altruism. It may draw on
emotions of fellow-feeling or solidarity (those frequently help), but it may
also entail quite hard-headed calculations of material advantage and
instrumental rationality. But the point is that, in this context, the interests
of the participants can be pursued, not
through exchange, but through actual (not virtual) cooperation. Furthermore, humans sometimes manage to build up
complex systems for enabling large-scale and sophisticated forms of
cooperation, including institutional mechanisms for collective deliberation and
decision-making, representation, etc.
(In the real
world, many human practices and institutions involve more or less complex
mixtures of elements from more than one of those categories, or even from all
three. But for the sake of conceptual clarity, and to avoid the characteristic
conceptual obfuscations, it's useful to begin by laying out those ideal-typical
analytical distinctions sharply. To pretend, or imply, or even tacitly
insinuate that option #2 is the only
way to coordinate human activity in sustained and beneficial ways—and that the only
conceivable alternative is gratuitous "benevolence"—is self-evidently
wrong.)
And as long as
we're on the subject of the tacit exclusions underlying Smith's foundational
false dichotomy, let me mention just one more factor. Smith suggests in the
passage you quoted that if we want someone else to do something that might be
necessary or beneficial for us, there are two kinds of motivation, and only two kinds of motivation, that we might appeal to. We can
appeal either to their individual self-interest or to their disinterested benevolence. Well, in the real world, we
often make claims or recommendations, or have expectations that we regard as
sensible and legitimate, based on people's obligations (moral, legal, customary, religious, or whatever).
Obligations are not individual
psychological characteristics, but socially structured norms, and they are not
simply reducible to motivations of generalized "benevolence" or of the calculation of individual
self-interest. (Of course, some people might want to argue for reducing them to
the latter—those would be the kinds of "rational actor" obsessives
who would tautologically reduce everything
to calculations of individual self-interest—but I don't think I need to spell
out to you the reasons why that won't work. Life is more complicated than
that.) Also, it so happens that systems of obligation are of fundamental
importance in shaping and coordinating all
modes and areas of human social life, from what Smith calls the "early and
rude state of society" up to the present. (I suppose that's a Durkheimian
point, though it might also be treated as Burkean or Polanyian.)
Smith might well
want to make the argument that coordinating human action through the market,
based on the motivations and practices of self-interested exchange (and their
indirect and unintended consequences), is (generally speaking, and all things
being equal) better and more efficient than coordinating human
action through domination, conscious coordination, obligation, etc. And one
could certainly find strong and plausible grounds for that argument (though I
confess to having a soft spot for conscious coordination, where practicable).
Nor is this
a peripheral or merely technical point. One of the central arguments that runs
through and structures Smith's whole discussion in Books I-II of WN is that
the market (based on the
built-in human motivations and "natural" practices of self-interested exchange) is not just one important basis of social order,
but is the fundamental
basis of social order (and of the main tendencies of long-term socio-historical
development). That's what it means to treat "exchange and its vicissitudes
as fundamental to human psychology and society".
Jeff Weintraub"
Comments
This an interesting and
instructive debate as one expects from Brad Delong and Jeff Weintraub, two
formidable scholars in the History of Economic Thought. The full text is available at http://jeffweintraub.blogspot.fr/2013/07/adam-smiths-conceptual-sleight-of-hand.html
and I highly recommend that you read it in full.
My critical
comments are necessarily concentrated on where I hold to another point of view.
First to a
question of tone. The title refers
to “sleight-of-hand”, which implies a deliberate deception of Smith’s part, or
at least a metaphorical or rhetorical debating point (Smith’s “cleverly deceptive, bits of conceptual and
rhetorical sleight-of-hand”). I am not naïve and where any shade of
deception is apparent I consider it appropriate to expose it, no matter who is found
to have behaved that way. However,
I do not think that Jeff has managed to do so on this occasion.
Smith was at a disadvantage
compared to Jeff in that the science of anthropology now counts hundreds of
thousands (possibly millions?) of papers, published and unpublished, many
on-line, revealing new aspects, new concepts, new behaviour sets, most of them
unknown to Smith. Also, close
observation by scientists of groups of chimpanzees, and other related species,
since Jane Goodhall led the way, and now scores of others, have also revealed
much new information certainly not available to Smith, nor to anybody else
until after the mid-20th century. I suggest that we should be careful when raising doubts
about Smith’s, or Brad Delong’s, scholarly integrity.
There is much else not raised
by Smith – and for that matter, Jeff too – in his presentation of other aspects
of human exchange behaviour when discussing starkly (for rhetorical effect)
Smith’s basic alternatives for encouraging an exchange transaction between men
and their dogs. Coming from a
family with strong links through his widowed mother, Smith narrowed his opening
example to a daily experience exceedingly common to many of his readers (and to
his young teenage students – for much of these chapters in WN came verbatim
from his Lectures in Jurisprudence, 1762-3, and were lifted into his WN). Dogs
abounded in their households. He
was not writing an exhaustive treatise. They would instantly recognise his
point and focus on the bargaining, which is wholly a human exchange behaviour,
that arose out of earlier (and still practised) behaviours, such as
reciprocity, alongside modern bargaining behaviours, using the conditional
proposition, identified by Smith in WN (I.ii.9-10): “Give me that which I want, and you shall have this
which you want”: “If-Then”, which
is experienced in global and street markets today.
[Since 1972 I have taught
negotiation workshops to practitioners, largely based on Smith’s conditional proposition
of bargaining; I have criticised modern economists (plus sociologists and
psychologists) for remaining ignorant of Smith’s 1776 pioneering statement in
WN of the essence of bargaining.]
I find Jeff unconvincing on
the essence of dog pack hunting behaviours. The essence of the pack chase is mutual co-operation, but it
is not intentional. If a dog sees a desirable target it will set off and chase
it; others nearby see the target, or are alerted to it by dogs joining a chase;
they too join the chase. A melee
commences as soon as one dog catches the target. The co-operation is limited to the chase; then its down to
every dog for itself). In chimp chases, the alpha males exert their brute
strength but other chimps stay close by to grab what they can and then fight to
hold to what they snatch.
It was not an exhaustive
account of the possibilities of co-operation that drove Smith’s account; it was
a legitimate teaching point that starkly reveals the importance of exchange
behaviour through bargaining, a wholly human behaviour (though some
primatologists have claimed to have observed –“sex-for meat” exchanges among
some chimpanzees).
On human exchanges,
reciprocation behaviour was and is very important. I call it the ‘quasi-bargain. It us observed in chimps, bats, and others, and certainly
among humans. See Robin Dunbar: “Gossip, Grooming and the Evolution of Language”
1997, 2nd ed. 2004).
Here the exchange is separated in time, compared to full bargains where
the exchange is simultaneously completed (mainly).
Smith in 1776 focussed on
benevolence as the alternative to self-interested bargaining. But self-interest, especially in the WN
“butcher, brewer, and baker” passage is woefully misunderstood, even by
distinguished scholars.
Two self-interested
bargainers would never reach an agreement by demanding their self-interested
offers were met in full. Moreover,
as is usually asserted, “benevolence” is not the alternative to
“self-interest”. It is “self
interest” which seems to be poorly understood.
I refer to Smith in Lectures on Jurisprudence: 219; 347; 493;
and Moral Sentiments: 17; 21; 22; 23, and set these with WN 26-27. Here, he makes it clear that bargaining
it is a process by which two bargainers mediate their different self-interests
as they understand them - we do not all share the same self-interests. He
advises the buyer to address the seller’s “self-love”, which involves
persuasion, and, of course, the seller also aims to persuade the buyer that the
proposals is in her best interests.
As they edge towards agreement they use persuasion by making small steps
to make their proposition more attractive.
Jeff suggests that
there are at least three ways to
achieve sustained coordination of human actions as: ‘top-down command’; ‘the market’; and ‘conscious cooperation’. From this restricted list, based on a selective view of
self-interest, he draws conclusions about Smith’s supposed dichotomy of only
benevolence or bargaining. But
Smith is discussing the ‘exchange propensity’, which does not limit all decision-making
in human societies to only two human phenomena.
There is the obvious world of politics, both personal and society wide. There are also laws of justice and
regulation, neither of which are normally negotiable nor bilaterally open to
acts of benevolence.
In so far as his theme was an
“inquiry into the nature and cause of the wealth of nations”, exchange was
bound to predominate. His “theory
of moral sentiments” was also bound the consider wider behavioural phenomena
than exchange. The ambit of his
views of ‘sustained co-ordination’ was not limited to explicit exchange, except
in some cases, and then when specified.
I am not sure that “the fundamental
basis of social order” is the market taking the long view of history. It is a relatively recent phenomenon
for most of the world’s population and its geographic dispersions, that began with the human disapora ‘out
of Africa’ long before even proto-markets existed. Those Homo sapiens (and before them pre-homo variants, such
as Homo Erectus, that left Africa perhaps c.1 million years earlier) reached
modern China and later, Australia, and crossed to North America, later Central
and South America, did not ‘co-ordinate’ using markets.
I agree with Jeff that the
debate with Brad is a “brilliant, powerful, and fascinating theoretical argument”. But I do not agree that Smith was “wrong”
and neither was it right that Jeff’s assertion that “swallowing” Smith’s argument at the
time and for the purposes of his Wealth Of Nations” has “led many very
intelligent people astray”. I make
no claims to be “very intelligent”
but I think I am closer to Smith’s honest purposes than Jeff is on this occasion.
2 Comments:
I find it amusing that Smith's arguments are unassailable because he was not privy to any future knowledge. This would be like discounting relativity because Newton was not aware of all knowledge after his death.
Smith had a knowledge of the world limited by his travels and readings. Does this discount the behaviors of all the other peoples of the world because they did not live in a European monarchy?
I'm afraid your argument falls flat as its basis is that Smith wasn't not wrong because he had no knowledge of the future and those relying on his words cannot be wrong because he was operating on a narrower world view than modern economists.
RC
Thank you for your observation.
However, I think that you may have misunderstood my point.
For deception, Smith would have had to deliberately known differently and suppressed the truth.
I suggested that a) he did not have the fuller information that we have today (dominance hierarchies, primate behaviours, pack hunting in the wild, etc.,), and b) he did comment on monkeys raiding an orchard for fruit in concert, and falling out over the non-peaceful division of the spoils.
Whereas hunting with dogs in fox hunts was more of an English than a Scottish experience, he may have witnessed one in his time at Oxford, where the concert of the chase ends in the melee of the kill.
My simple point is that many of today’s authorities comment on the failings of their past predecessors using modern data to make their point and a little more humility rather than unscholarly triumphalism may be more appropriate.
The issue surely is the appreciation of what our predecessors brought forward on the basis of their existing and new knowledge. Not to criticise them for alleged “deception”.
Gavin
Post a Comment
<< Home