Mathematical Truths Do Not Make Untrue Assumptions in Economics True
Tim Johnston, is a Lecturer in
Financial Mathematics at Heriot-Watt University in
Edinburgh. (Heriot-Watt was the first UK university to offer degrees in
Actuarial Science and Financial Mathematics and is a leading UK research centre
in the fields). He posted this article in “Magic , Maths and Money” HERE
“How economics suffers from de-politicised
mathematics”
“Financial economics produced
sophisticated mathematical theorems related to pricing and risk management
in the derivative markets and simply by existing as mathematics they
were legitimate. There was no room for debate or discussion because
mathematics, based on Hilbert’s formal deduction and Bourbaki’s idealised
abstractions, and written in obscure notation, was infallible. It doesn't seem
to matter that there were discussion and concerns within mathematics,
economics accepted the authority of the theorems and their models
simply because they were mathematical.
I have not yet come across what I feel is a
credible reason why economics has become so enamored with formalist
mathematics. Lawson [7, Ch 10] argues it is because
mathematics confers authority, but gives no explanation as to why mathematics
should have this power. Lawson challenges the power but one senses that he
feels mathematics exists independently of human thought, and this mathematics
is irrelevant to social phenomena. He does not seem to think that mathematics
could be a product of economic intuition, not just physical
intuition. Weitntraub [14] offers a narrative of how mathematical
ideas crossed over into economics, without giving what I think is a compelling
argument as to why mathematical formalism became so significant. Mirowski
argues that ‘Cyborg science’, did not spontaneously emerge but was “constructed
by a new breed of science managers” [9, p 15] and it was these managers that
promoted the mathematisation of economics. While the emergence of ‘Cyborg
science’ as a dominant theme of post-war science may well have been
constructed, there is something spontaneous in Wiener, Turing and
Kolmogorov, the leading twentieth century mathematicians of the US, UK and
USSR, all independently having a youthful interest in biology, becoming
mathematicians and making contributions in probability and going on to work in
computation.
My own belief is that the critical process
was the interaction between (particularly American) economists and
mathematicians in the Second World War working on problems of Operations
Research. At the outbreak of the war in 1939 the vast majority of soldiers and
politicians would not have thought mathematicians had much to offer the war
effort, the attitude among the military is still often that “war is a human
activity that cannot be reduced to mathematical formulae” [12, p 3]. However, operational researchers
had laid the foundations for Britain’s survival in the dark days of 1940-1941,
Turing and his code-breakers had enabled the allies to keep one step ahead of
the Nazis and Allied scientists had ensured that the scarce resources of men
and arms were effectively allocated to achieving different objectives. Alan
Bullock argues that the blitzkrieg was the only military tactic available to
the Nazis, since they had neither the capability nor the capacity to manage
more complex operations [2, pp 588–594]. By the end of the war, it
could be argued that the war had been won as much through the efforts of
awkward engineers as square-jawed commandos and the Supreme Commander of Allied
Forces in Europe and Chief of the U.S. Army, General Eisenhower was calling for
more scientists to support the military [12, p 64].
It is hardly surprising that in the post-war
years economists embraced mathematics. Pre-war generals would have made the
same sort of objections to mathematics that economists had. However, after the
war the success of Operations Research could be compared to the failure of
economists in the lead up to, and in the aftermath of, the Great Depression
that had dominated the decade before the war. But possibly more significant
than this theory is the fact that many post-war economists had worked alongside
mathematicians on military and government policy problems during the war.
Samuelson who was instrumental in introducing stochastic calculus had worked in
Wiener’s lab at MIT addressing gun-control problems during the war [8, p 63–64].
Personally I feel prominent economists
became over awed by the successes of mathematics, through, for example,
observing mathematicians’ abilities to transform apparently random sequences of
letters into meaningful messages, something that must have seemed magical and
resonant to the economic problem of interpreting data. The problem is codes are
generated deterministically but the same cannot be said for economic
data. I believe it was a synthesis of the post First World War traumas of
mathematics and the post-Second World War optimism and confidence of
economics that created the explosion of mathematical economics in the
1950s-1960s.
Today mathematical finance is possibly the
most abstract branch of applied mathematics, while mathematical physics is
complex it is still connected to sensible phenomena and amenable to intuition,
and this state seems to be typical of the relationship between
mathematics and economics. The situation is not irrecoverable, but, as I
have said before, it requires a much tighter integration of non-mathematical
economists and un-economic mathematicians. I look with envy at my
colleagues carrying out research in biology using the same
mathematical technology I use but, as one said recently, their papers
do not need to prove a theorem and clear results are admired, not
technical brilliance.”
Refs:
[7] T. Lawson. Reorienting Economics. Taylor & Francis, 2012.
[8] D. MacKenzie. An Engine, Not a Camera: How Financial Models Shape Markets. The
MIT Press, 2008.
[9] P. Mirowski. Machine dreams: Economic
agents as cyborgs. History of
Political Economy,
29(1):13–40, 1998.
[10] PCBS. Changing Banking for Good.
Technical report, The Parliamentary Commission on Banking Standards, 2013.
[11] Y. Rav. A critique of a
formalist-mechanist version of the justification of arguments in
mathematicians’ proof practices. Philosophia
Mathematica, 15(3):291–320, 2007.
[12] C. R. Schrader. History of Operations Research in the United States Army, Volume
I: 1942–1962. U. S. Government
Printing Office, 2006.
[13] I. Stewart. Bye–Bye Bourbaki: Paradigm
shifts in mathematics. The
Mathematical Gazette,
79(486):496–498, 1995.
[14] E. R. Weintraub. How Economics Became a Mathematical Science.
Duke University Press, 2002.
Comment
The above is an extract from a much longer
post discussing aspects of the history of formalised theorems in post 19th-century
maths and should be consulted to see where Tim Johnston places his interesting
ideas about the consequential shadow of maths in economic thinking, or more
particularly, in financial economics.
I tend to agree with Tim Johnston’s general
slant (noticing that he is on the faculty of Heriot-Watt University from which
I retired in 2005 after 33 years in the Department of Finance and Edinburgh
Business School; I have not yet met him).
Broadly, I am remain sceptical of the
arrogance of mathematical exponents in economics and their related
philosophical ideology of ‘Max U’ thinking that dominated economics since the
last quarter of the 19th century. Economic theory is not made any
truer by maths. It is a basic error to project mathematical treatment as true
of the real world.
Maximisation of utility ideas grip
mainstream thinking. If individuals
are assumed to behave as if maximising utility theories are true in the real
world, when they may not be true outside the assumption that they are, then
even if the maths are true, the assumption of ‘MaxU’ may very well remain
untrue.
On their own terms the maths of ‘MaxU’ are
unassailable; on any terms ‘MaxU’ is not true of the real world. Moreover, making decisions based upon
the truth of predictions that may very well not be true, is dangerous, as the
recent global financial crisis illustrates.
(Hat Tip to Mark
Thoma HERE)
4 Comments:
"I feel prominent economists became over awed by the successes of mathematics"
Maybe I'm dumb. Could very well be.
"successes of mathematics" seems ridiculous. Have there been failures of mathematics?
I get that this is about a perceived over-mathematization of economics. Lots of good stuff written about this; see, eg, Noah Smith (http://is.gd/LdjgrL). But I don't see the actual point of the present post. Is it "I have not yet come across what I feel is a credible reason why economics has become so enamored with formalist mathematics."? This seems pretty obvious; in fact some of the reasons are mentioned above, then, for some reason, discarded.
As said, I'm probably dumb.
The GIGO (garbage in garbage out) principle applies to math. Invariably in math one has assumptions, and one sees what follows from those assumption. Nevertheless, the conclusions are only as valid as the assumptions.
If y=4x and x=2, then y=8 (using standard multiplication of ordinary numbers) -- period. Nevertheless, we still have both assumptions, y=4x and x=2. The conclusion is only as valid as the assumptions.
In economics, if people use idiotic assumptions about human behavior it doesn't matter how good the math is. Furthermore, I've seen horrible math -- innumeracy -- in certain economics schools, mainly about exponential population growth facing limited resources.
Some things I've seen in economics and math remind me of Richard Feynman's experience with physics in Brazil. (See "Surely You're Joking, Mr. Feynman".)
Vitus Capital
Thanks for your comments.
Posts address different readers. Not all agree with them. Some consider a post unnecessary or wrong. Others agree.
I am not sure in your case which of many sub-groups yours falls into.
Maths, like formal logic, has limits when applied to explain human behaviour. Those limits are not as wide as behaviours can be. That's all.
Gavin
John Randomness
Agreed.
Applying philosophy to people likewise. Homo economicus rationality and marginal utility is a case in point too.
Learning it is a useful teaching idea in basic economics. Believing it as the real world is not. Histories of human societies are also useful but not sufficient. Humans are a complex species, with histories and a capacity for reasoning and discussing; the original faculties noted by Adam Smith at the beginning of Wealth Of Nations as the basis for exchange behaviour, from which economic behaviour evolved.
Gavin
Post a Comment
<< Home