How Not to Explain Economics to Anthropologists - and to Some Economists
From Rex in “Savage
Minds Backup” on “How to
explain anthropology to a physicist"
“Science works by proposing and disposing of
hypotheses. Hypotheses come from a lot of places: previous research results,
modeling, inspiration, and plain old intuition. Our intuition is a good source
of scientific hypotheses because our species has evolved to possess an implicit
model of the natural world that allows us to move, eat, balance, and so forth.
Of course, this model is not perfect nor is it explicit. Which is why we need
science. Nevertheless, it is a good source of hypotheses, and our intuitions
about where things go when we throw them are an excellent place to begin
elaborating, say, a classical mechanical account of projectile motion,
regardless of where in the world you are when you throw something. This is
because physical laws operate uniformly on earth, modulo extremely advanced
concerns in quantum physics or the philosophy of science.”
Comments
I could not help thinking about how to explain
the political economy of Adam Smith to a modern neo-classical economist let
alone to an anthropologist, never mind the even more challenging difficulties
of explaining it to a physicist.
Frankly, they just can’t get it.
Everybody being out of step except for the
proverbial “Jock” (a well-worn phrase in the colloquial Scot’s culture of earlier
generations) doesn’t quite capture the dilemma faced by many Smithian scholars,
including those very few modern economists who have actually read Smith’s
Works.
Smith turned his mind to scientific
hypothesising in 1744 as a 21 year-old student at Oxford University, where he
had some sort of life-changing experience causing him to drop out of his
theology course leading to ordination into the Church of England in favour of
the Juris course leading to the uncertain preferment of teaching.
All his life from 1744 Smith remained
sceptical of Oxford’s academic culture where the faculty had “given up the
pretence of teaching” and students largely were left to read alone and teach
themselves, only obliged to attend prayers twice a day and a “lecture” once a
week.
His life change took the form of his writing for his own satisfaction a long essay on the “History of Astronomy” (HOA), which he completed before
1758. Thereafter he kept his essay
in his bedroom bureau all his life and apparently told no one of its existence,
including his close friend, David Hume, who first learnt of its existence in
1773, 22 years after they met in 1751.
Moreover, his HOA, was saved from the
destruction of almost all of his other essays, unfinished manuscripts and
miscellaneous papers on his personal instructions a few days before he died in
1790. Therefore we may safely conclude that the HOA essay had special personal
importance for Smith.
Most readers take the HOA at face value as
a history of astronomy with some remarks at the beginning on “savage” and
pagan ideas about natural events, many of them likely to frighten the ignorant
into beliefs about malevolent invisible spirits, and gods tormenting those who
annoy them, and generally ruling humans with lightning bolts and other
disasters.
My own take on the HOA is that it signals
when Smith ceased to believe in religious explanations for anything, except in
the imaginations of the gullible, including the rigid beliefs of revealed
religion. In this latter, he was
shocked to conclude that Calvinism shared the same basic theological "heresies" against human intelligence as the Catholic "superstitions" (while the Church of Scotland behaved better than Roman Catholics, and even better than the Church of England).
While he had no problem with publically condemning the decadent
ignorant superstitions of Roman Catholics – after all he was brought up in a Calvinist
household by his religious mother whom he adored and could never hurt by
revealing his changed views – he had a major problem of concealing his new
philosophical conclusions from Calvinist zealots. Hence,
he went to the lengths he did to avoid saying or doing anything in public that
would cause her embarrassment from any wilful behaviour on his part brought to her attention in the inevitable public controversies of doing so (his three predecessors as in the Chair of Moral Philosophy were each hauled before the zealots who dominated the Glasgow Presbytery).
Returning to the paragraph quoted from “Rex”
above, I was struck by the sentence: “This is because physical laws operate
uniformly on earth, modulo extremely advanced concerns in quantum physics or
the philosophy of science.”
Yes, but what of social “laws”? What of the dissimilarity of individual
human behaviours? Do these
“operate uniformly on earth”? Do
people in the same family act “uniformly”, or in different generations, or in different cultures?
We may expect a carbon atom to operate
uniformly across the planet, or any other planet in this solar system or any
other planet in any other solar system in the universe or any earlier or
succeeding or preceding universe.
But of humans on this planet, now or earlier or in succeeding generations, can
we assert or act upon the assumption of “uniformity”? I don’t think so.
This means that observations may identify
broad trends and possible or potential outcomes but the precision and endurance
of possible conclusions that follow may not have the stability expected in
physics across the universe.
Briefly, humans may and can “game” the system, either benevolently or
selfishly, not necessarily immediately, but possibly later if not sooner.
This is not about denying the value of
hypothesising, collecting data, and subjecting it to the usual statistical
testing, and such like nor against experimenting with mathematical processes
and such like. I am against that
science that comes to believe because something can be represented by maths that
it is the real world.
That Debreu “proved” that a general
equilibrium solution can be “proved” is not proof of the proposition that
therefore such a GE solution was possible in a real world economy. Worse, many
modern economists believe with a frightening and sincere certainty that Adam
Smith was near to saying so.
Fortunately for their lasting reputation, other modern economists, like
Mark Blaug, robustly refuted such nonsense (Blaug unlike others had actually
read and studied Adam Smith’s Works).
It remains my lasting disappointment that
many anthropologists, whose work I read regularly, seem to have adopted the
modern version of Adam Smith (on bargaining, self-interest, and even the
invisible hand metaphor). I do
hope they do not look for mathematical “immutable” laws of human behaviour thinking that to
do so is the route to “hard science”.
I suggest that their reading of the first
parts of Smith’s HOA might give them pause for thought. The same goes for modern economists,
though come to think of it some of them miss Smith’s point spectacularly
(I am thinking here particularly of N. E. Aydinonat, 2008. The Invisible Hand
in Economics: how economists explain unintended consequences, Oxford,
Routledge).
2 Comments:
This post makes one thing about which or whom anticipated who or what first. Did the physical world anticipated humans or did humans anticipated the physical world?
Einstein wondered " whether God had any choice in the creation of the world". The question seems to suggest that the physical world was developed to accommodated humans.
Gavin,
Do you know of any anthropologist that talks or understands economics, about housekeeping, resource renewal and distribution?
Post a Comment
<< Home