Chris Dillow Asks: Why Study Classical Economic Thought?
Chris Dillow, a respected economist with a strong suit in mathematics, but with his feet firmly
on the ground and a highly sensitive antenna to detect high-blown crap, blogs
at “Stumbling and Mumbling” (“an extremist, not a fanatic”), and today it carries
a typical well written and well argued piece, “WHY STUDY CLASSICAL
ECONOMIC THOUGHT? HERE
“Simon says economists should study the history of
economic thought. I'm with him: my masters' dissertation was on Malthus's
theory of unemployment. But this poses the question: why bother with the wrong
ideas of dead men?
One answer is that they weren't always wrong. Marx was
right about quite a lot. Mill
can be read profitably by anyone worrying about the consequences of
a low-growth economy; Ricardo anticipated today's debates about automation; and you can read the rise in
commodity prices and fall in equity valuations of the last 10 years as being
consistent with his theory of rent and profits.
And sometimes, the difference between the classics and
modern economists is not that the latter are right and the former wrong, but
rather that they address different questions. Ricardo didn't much care about
year-to-year fluctuations in GDP but did worry a lot about the determinants of
the distribution of income. Many economists today have the opposite priorities.
This, though, means their abilities to address Ricardian and Marxian issues
have ossified. If you read Greg Mankiw's defence (pdf) of the 1%, you'll not get the
impression that today's economists have a much better understanding of the distribution of income
than Ricardo or Marx did.
In fact, in one sense economists are only now
rediscovering what the classics knew. All of them, from Smith with his
invisible hand through to Marx, were concerned with the question of how some
kind of order emerged from what looked like a chaotic process of millions of
people exchanging millions of goods. To Smith, this order was benign, to Marx
less so. But both agreed on the importance of the question: how does order
emerge from millions of individual decisions? Neither thought that a
"Robinson Crusoe economy" made sense. It is only quite recently, with
the growth of interest in markets as emergent
evolutionary (pdf) ecosystems (pdf) that this issue has
returned to the forefront of economics.
This raises the question: in what ways has economics
progressed? One answer is that we've gathered more hard data than the classics
had; Smith, for example, relied almost solely on anecdote. Another, obvious,
answer is that we have vastly more mathematical formalism than they did. But
what is the value of such formalism. Could it be that there are some questions
which can't be answered solely by reliance on mathematical technique? Studying
the classics reminds us that there are potentially more tools in the
economists' shed than maths alone.
What's more, even when the classics are wrong, knowing
why can sharpen our understanding. For example, everyone from Malthus to Marx
expected the economy to converge to a state of zero growth. This view has been
wrong (so far!) because technical progress has won the race against diminishing
returns. But this should force us to ask about the determinants of such
technical progress; why is this more powerful than the classics thought? It is
only quite recently - with the emergence of endogenous growth theories - that
economists have progressed from Malthus; the old neoclassical growth models merely assumed
technical progress which is no explanation at all of the classics' failure.
And herein lines another reason why the classics
matter. They were the smartest people of their day. If they were wrong or
confused, isn't it also likely that the best minds our day might also be
mistaken and inadequate? The idea that we are clever and our forebears stupid
is surely just arrogant gibberish. The mere passage of time does not ensure
that progress happens. If this were the case, we'd have to believe Rihanna is a
better singer than Bessie Smith was. And nobody believes that.”
Comment
I agree with the theme but not every detail. I tend to pick and mix Chris Dillow’s
posts, not being interested in such as the debate or exposition of Sraffa’s or
Ricardo’s theories. I agree that “the
difference between the classics and modern economists is not that the latter
[former] are right and the former [latter] wrong, but rather that they address
different questions”.
I suggests that the understanding the classics gives
us an opportunity to see where modern economists have taken economics and to
think through where they might have done differently to avoid the dead ends of
much of what is taught today in consequence.
The classical economists in the main wrote of an
economy closer to what happened in practice than today’s economists, though
they had their pure theorists among them. Chris “poses the question: why bother
with the wrong ideas of dead men?”
I agree in part; uncovering where dead men went wrong and why are
necessary obligations of living towards the dead, as is asking: why bother with
the wrong ideas of living men?
Moreover, when Chris asks: “in what ways has economics
progressed? One answer is that we've gathered more hard data than the classics
had; Smith, for example, relied almost solely on anecdote”, I am bound to feel
unease with first part of the statement because there is plenty of data in
Smith’s Wealth Of Nations, prompting some modern readers to query their
relevance, and dismay with his describing the last part as “almost solely
anecdote”. An historical approach is not a tenuous or irrelevant anecdote, Chris.
Today’s over “reliance on mathematical technique” is a
worse fad, in my view. ‘MaxU’
economics is a useful set of ideas to test understanding and standards; less so
to teach about the real world, where equilibrium is not stable and thereby
isn’t attainable as and state.
Add into the modern mix the role of competing
ideologies that block off experiment to find what does and what doesn’t work and
you have a recipe for predetermined, usually wrong, answers to quite basic
questions. Smith for example,
suggested as much in regard to a debate about the management of toll roads:
should they be managed by public servants or by private managers? He outlined the drawbacks of both. Today they would debate the issue in
parliament with predictable stances across the aisles and, if delegated to
local government, the chosen decisions would follow the political colour of
local parties and not an intentional predisposition to experiment. I think Smith’s sort of pragmatic thinking suggests a means
to break the deadlock; experiment and then decide on the next experimental
phases or variations. The debate
over privatization versus public ownership and management is a lottery weighted
by which ideology dominates parliament.
Hence, I welcome Chris Dillow’s contribution and
recommend readers to bookmark his Blog and select from its active menu topics
that interest you.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home