Keynes on Laissez-Faire
I
read the Keynes quote below in Brad Delong’s Blog HERE and from that lead read: “As
John Maynard Keynes shrilly stated back in 1926”: “Let us
clear… the ground…. It is not true that individuals possess a prescriptive
'natural liberty' in their economic activities. There is no 'compact'
conferring perpetual rights on those who Have or on those who Acquire. The
world is not so governed from above that private and social interest always
coincide. It is not so managed here below that in practice they coincide. It is
not a correct deduction from the principles of economics that enlightened
self-interest always operates in the public interest. Nor is it true that
self-interest generally is enlightened… individuals… promot[ing] their own ends
are too ignorant or too weak to attain even these. Experience does not show
that… social unit[s] are always less clear-sighted than [individuals] act[ing]
separately. We [must] therefore settle… on its merits… "determin[ing] what
the State ought to take upon itself to direct by the public wisdom, and what it
ought to leave, with as little interference as possible, to individual
exertion".
Comment
My “Collected
Writings of John Maynard Keynes” are kept in France, so I was able to re-read
“The End of Laissez-Faire” from Volume IX: “Essays in Persuasion” (pp 272-94. Macmillan).
The paragraph
quoted by Brad Delong is fairly typical of the tone and language of the
Essay. While Keynes’s main focus
is on laissez-faire, it also strikes at the general proposition now widespread
across the discipline, usually wrapped in the extreme neoclassical fable that:
[Adam] “Smith
proclaimed the principle of the ‘Invisible Hand’; every individual in pursuing
his own selfish good was led, as if by an invisible hand, to achieve the best
good for all, so that any interference with free competition by government was
almost certain to be injurious” (Samuelson, “Economics: an introductory
analysis”, 5th edition,
McGraw-Hill, p 39).
Keynes,
rightly, points out that Adam Smith never used the words laissez-faire. And on the single occasion where he
used the IH metaphor in Wealth Of Nations, it is a travesty to impute, let
alone blatantly assert, that his words can be stretched to mean what
Samuelson’s wild inference takes them to mean.
However, on
this occasion I shall not develop that theme.
I want to
return to laissez-faire, accepting how Keynes expresses his demolition of the
popular idea that laissez faire has or ought to have traction in it. I completely agree. And before my libertarian friends jump
on me, I should point out that the meaning drawn from the incident between the
merchant, Legendre and the French Minister, Colbert, is not entirely innocent
of a narrow self interest.
‘Laissez-nous
faire’ is not advocated as a universal principle for merchants and their
customers; it was a very partial principle for merchants only – “laissez-nous
faire” cries Legendre (“leave us alone!”). And that is the point of my own libertarian reservations
about the slogan itself and its origins.
French
markets were highly regulated and supervised by government inspectors. Yes, I agree an abomination. This placed consumers at the mercy of
the decisions of local magistrates.
Freeing merchants from the administrative burdens of the inspectors
could, indeed, be a tentative step forward but freeing merchants from
interference from competing merchants puts consumers at the mercy of the
intentions of the merchants, which, as experience shows, is a high-risk
strategy and generally one that has woeful consequences. As it was, experience in England and
Scotland had been deeply marked by the monopolizing consequences of merchant
tradesmen free, under governments, through the dead-hand of the Guilds in towns
where they held sway, and ruthlessly protected by the Apprenticeship Acts that
virtually eliminated competition.
No laissez-faire there!
Moreover,
laissez-faire became the rallying cry for merchants and industrialists in the
19th century to rally support for resisting government legislation
against the excessive hours in mills and mines and the employment of very young
children and women. It was also
the common slogan of the anti-corn law agitation aimed at lowering the wages of
labourers under the guise of removing barriers to farm imports.
Neither of
these laissez-faire campaigns were the disinterested motives of the beneficiaries. Mill owners preferred
laissez-faire to protect themselves from interference in the arduous, unsafe employment
conditions and long hours they imposed on the males, females and children whom
they employed; Mine owners likewise employed women and children underground at
lower wages than adult men. Both
wrapped themselves in laissez-faire flags to wipe up the blood of their
employees when they demanded their own freedoms and not those of their
labourers or their customers.
On these
issues I agree with Keynes.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home