Larry Arnhart On Adam Smith On Exchange
Larry
Arnhart Blogs at Darwinian Conservatism HERE http://darwinianconservatism.blogspot.co.uk/ writes a most interesting piece on the significance of Adam Smith’s recognition
of the key role of what he called the “propensity to truck, barter, and trade”
in human societies. It is rather
long post.
“I remember the
first time” [reports Larry] “that I read Adam Smith's claim in The Wealth of Nations that the
"propensity to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another" is
uniquely human and not found in any other animals. I wondered whether
this was true, and, if true, what it would mean for our understanding of human
social life.
… Haim Ofek (Second Nature: Economic Origins of Human
Evolution) and Matt Ridley (The
Rational Optimist) have argued that what we now know about human
evolution confirms Smith's insight about the unique importance of exchange for
human history. The whole of human history for the past 200,000 years can
be understood as the progressive extension of human cooperation through exchange
and the division of labor--from foraging bands to agrarian states to modern
commercial societies in global networks of trade. Both Ofek and Ridley
see this as arising from a human propensity to exchange that cannot
be seen in any other animal. And yet I am still trying to make up my
mind about this.
In The Wealth of Nations, Smith explains
the division of labor as the primary cause for the increasing productivity of
labor, which includes the famous example of the pin factory. In the
second chapter, he explains how this division of labor arises in human history.
"This
division of labour, from which so many advantages are derived, is not
originally the effect of any human wisdom, which foresees and intends that
general opulence to which it gives occasion. It is the necessary, though
very slow and gradual consequence of a certain propensity in human nature
which has in view no such extensive utility; the propensity to truck, barter,
and exchange one thing for another.
"Whether this
propensity be one of those original principles in human nature, of which no
further account can be given; or whether, as seems more probable, it be the
necessary consequence of the faculties of reason and speech … It is
common to all men, and to be found in no other race of animals, which seem to
know neither this nor any other species of contracts. … [Man] In
civilized society he stands at all times in need of the cooperation and
assistance of great multitudes, while his whole life is scarce sufficient to
gain the friendship of a few persons. In almost every other race of
animals each individual, when it is gown up to maturity, is entirely
independent, and in its natural state has occasion for the assistance of no
other living creature. But man has almost constant occasion for the help
of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to expect it from their benevolence
only. He will be more likely to prevail if he can interest their
self-love in his favour, and shew them that it is for their own advantage to do
for him what he requires of them. Whoever offers to another a bargain of
any kind, proposes to do this. Give me that which I want, and you shall
have this which you want, is the meaning of every such offer; and it is in this
manner that we obtain from one another the far greater part of those good
offices which we stand in need of. It is not from the benevolence of the
butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their
regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity
but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own necessities but of
their advantages.” [WN I.ii.] …
[In] this passage,
we see the fundamental idea that is common to Smith's social thought and
Darwin's biology--the possibility of design-without-a-designer ("not
originally the effect of any human wisdom") through emergent or
spontaneous order.
Smith [asks]: Was
the propensity to exchange an original principle of human evolution, or was it
a late by-product of earlier evolved "faculties of reason and speech"? [He]
considers it more probable that
reason and speech came first, and then the propensity to exchange came later as
a by-product. In the Lectures on
Jurisprudence, Smith says that the "real foundation" of
exchange and the division of labor is "that principle to persuade which so
much prevails in human nature." [GK: This notion is expanded in
Moral Sentiments in a manner entirely relevant for traded bargaining.] Like
Aristotle, Smith seems to believe that human beings are more political than
other political animals because human beings have a capacity for logos--reason or speech--that allows
them to persuade one another to cooperate for common ends, which makes exchange
and the division of labor possible. Ofek argues, however, that the
evidence of human evolutionary history now suggests that exchange was an early
agent of human evolution that favored the evolution of human reason and speech. … Non-human animals are unable to communicate with one another well
enough to say: "this is mine, that yours; I am willing to give this for
that." … In human civilization, individuals need
"the cooperation and assistance of great multitudes," and for this
they must appeal not to benevolence but to self-love, by persuading other
individuals to engage with them in mutually beneficial exchanges.
… Remarkably,
Darwin says almost nothing about exchange in human evolution. But there
are at least two passages in Darwin's writings that both Ofek and Ridley cite
as supporting their arguments about the human evolution of exchange. … Darwin describes the savage people that he saw at Tierra del
Fuego. He reports: "Some of the Fuegians plainly showed that they
had a fair notion of barter. I gave one man a large nail (a most valuable
present) without making any signs for a return; but he immediately picked out
two fish, and handed them up on the point of his spear. If any present
was designed for one canoe, and it fell near another, it was invariably given
to the right owner." Darwin seems, then, to agree with Smith that
even those living in the most primitive foraging societies show "the
propensity to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another."
In The Descent of Man, Darwin
describes how man became "the most dominant animal" through
technological inventions such as tools. … Although
he doesn't make it explicit, Darwin implies that the complexity of
artifacts in the archaeological record could be interpreted as evidence for a
division of labor that promotes the dexterity and inventiveness that comes from
specialization. Ofek and Ridley have adopted this line of reasoning
in arguing that the explosion of technological complexity in the Upper
Paleolithic record of human evolution is a
consequence of exchange and specialization, which is confirmed by evidence
that some of the material in the human artifacts was transported over long
distances, apparently by trade.
… Other animals
cooperate with one another based on kinship, relatedness, and reciprocity
(direct and indirect), and human cooperation show these same evolved mechanisms
at work. But cooperation based on exchange or barter is uniquely human,
and it cannot be explained as a form of reciprocity. Reciprocity means
giving each other the same thing. I'll scratch your back if you scratch
mine (direct reciprocity). Or I'll scratch your back because you have a
reputation for scratching the backs of others (indirect reciprocity). But
exchange means giving each other different things. As Smith puts it,
"Give me that which I want, and you shall have this which you
want." Other animals can't do this.
… Ridley cites
some experiments with chimpanzees: "The primatologist Sarah Brosnan tried to teach two different
groups of chimpanzees about barter and found it very problematic. Her
chimps preferred grapes to apples to cucumbers to carrots (which they liked
least of all). They were prepared sometimes to give up carrots for
grapes, but they almost never bartered apples for grapes (or vice versa),
however advantageous the bargain. They could not see the point of giving
up food they liked for food they liked even more. True barter requires
that you give up something you value in exchange for something else you value
slightly more." (59)
It seems to me
though that Ridley is obscuring some of the complexity in these experiments … Brosnan
and her colleagues apparently showed that chimps do barter, at least in a
situation where they can trade very low valued items
(carrots) for very high valued items (grapes). [Chimps] not barter where
the gains from barter are small--as in trading valuable apples for
slightly more valuable grapes. One possible explanation that they
suggest is that the chimps are less inclined to take the risk from giving up a
valued food item if the possible gains are too small.
Nevertheless, it
does seem that these experiments provide some support for the Smith/Ridley
position. [Chimps] don't seem to spontaneously barter in the wild.
This is in contrast to the human situation where bartering seems to come easily
as a spontaneous behavior, even in the most primitive human conditions, as with
Darwin's Fuegians.
It's still not
clear to me, however, that Ridley has successfully distinguished exchange
from reciprocity. In fact, sometimes Ridley explains exchange as based on
trustworthy reputation, and thus indirect reciprocity (see Ridley,
93-104).”
Comment
Larry Arnhart’s contribution
parallels some of my own research and writing of some years ago (unpublished,
alas), “The Pre-History of Bargaining” (2003). On the whole, despite some quibbles, Larry Arnhart’s thesis is
very helpful.
Many modern social
science scholars (including too many economists) misread Adam Smith’s chapter 2
of Wealth Of Nations (see my Lost Legacy post from yesterday as a prime
example). Others write without
evidence that they take from Adam Smith on “truck, barter, and exchange”. Some, such as Dr David Graeber, of Yale
and London Universities, attack Smith from not anticipating 200 years of
subsequent field research by anthropologists, most of whom have instant access
to recent research numbered in the thousands without moving from their desks,
from which Dr Graeber concludes that Smith wrote a load of nonsense about
“barter”, on the ground that it is not common among hunter-gatherers studied
today, and is not reported as existing from much field research. Others beside anthropologists,
including Dr Graeber, do not understand Smith’s meaning of “exchange”; they
narrowly interpret exchange as being about bargaining in the modern sense. Sometimes they slip into rewriting
Smith’s “truck, barter, and exchange” as “truck, barter, and trade” (from
memory I think Karl Polanyi did this once in his The Great Transformation,
1944).
Smith’s central
concept of the generality of “exchange” appears in his earliest writings on the
origins of language (1761). Two
strangers able to speak but not sharing a common language (specific sounds
associated with objects) engage in developing an agreed language from the most
primitive noun-only sounds, and so on to adjectives, verbs, etc. There is a minimum requirement for
agreement on meaning – this sound means that object, a tree or a cave and so
on; that sound means danger. Even
chimps, birds and such like, seem to have recognizable calls for danger that
are specific to their species in specific localities. For humans this was the beginning of
mutually intelligible language by agreement from exchange among co-specifics in
a locality – languages were (are) numerous around the globe (40,000 languages
among Australian aborigines in the 19th century).
For Smith, exchange
was a common phenomenon. He did
not make the mistake of believing that exchange was about “equivalents” of a
common value (whatever that means), and nor does one party have to try to gain
“more” than the “other’, whatever that means with incommensurable entities.
What I give up in a bargained exchange may be valued less by me than what I
accept in exchange as of more value to me and vice versa. What we exchange is valued differently
at the moment of the exchange because if it is valued the same, why bother
exchanging? I wonder sometimes
just how much attention some anthropologists pay to what they are doing when
they bargain? In this conundrum
the entire theory of surplus value is suspect. Exchange is a two-way process.
When Captains Cook,
Bligh and others, took their ships into Matavi Bay, Tahiti in the 18th century,
the most popular European among the hundred or so sailors was the ship’s armourer,
whose forge on shore, shaped the nails that the islanders received in exchanges
with seamen (usually for sex with female islanders [A wag once described the
transaction as “a screw for a nail”]) and made iron nails into something more
useful for islanders. There
was no iron on the Pacific islands, and local products, such as spear-heads,
knives, or spade heads, were made from wood or stones. In time, there was a
downside for the islanders because the seamen brought with them venereal
disease, which spread rapidly in the Tahitian Island group, and iron weapons
proved too effective for killing local enemies, which also reduced the
population.
I would qualify
Larry’s observation that “Reciprocity means giving each other the same
thing”. Does it? Reciprocal acts
are not the same thing when considered as actions separated in time. Apes groom as ordered by the Alpha
male, but they also engaged in discretionary grooming not based on Alpha power. There are grooming circles in which
certain apes groom other apes on a discretionary basis. As grooming takes up to three hours,
there is insufficient time in a day to spend six hours in reciprocal
grooming. Should an ape groom an
ape and days later that ape does not reciprocate in grooming the original
groomer, the disappointed ape refuses to groom that ape ever again.
In human
reciprocation similar behaviour is noted. A work-colleague who gives another lift to the station
in heavy rain (or some such action like, feeding a neighbour’s cat or watering
a colleague’s office plants, etc.,) is expected to reciprocate should the
situation need to be reversed.
However, a failure to do so, breaks the reciprocal partnership, which
leaves the colleague to walk in the rain, or the cat or the plants die,
whatever the original motivation for the beneficial act, including altruism. The different time and place for
a reciprocal act adds an inescapable quality to the apparent sameness of the
transactions. They are not the
same, which is why I say reciprocation is a “quasi-bargain”. They are deep in human behaviour and anthropologists
agree that they preceded bargaining exchanges in the 200 thousand years of human
pre- and recorded history.
Please follow the
link HERE and read a useful contribution to Adam Smith’s understanding of bargaining.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home